To
radicalize an idea, ideal or claim about reality is to believe the
idea, ideal, or reality claim should always be held to be true or it
should always be advanced above all other views or choices. This
view or choice is determined to be the most appropriate, irrespective
of the particular factors involved in any given situation under which
the idea, ideal or reality claim becomes relevant. For example, in a
given situation, if I radicalize the ideal of liberty, I would choose
the option that promotes liberty no matter what else is going on. In
terms of liberty, the most clearly stated expression of a radicalized
view was issued by the presidential candidate, Barry Goldwater, when
he stated, “I would remind you that extremism in the defense of
liberty is no vice!” People also forget that in his very next
sentence, he doubled down his extremism by stating, “And let me
remind you also that moderation in the pursuit of justice is no
virtue!” Of course, one needs to define terms – like what we
mean by liberty or justice – but however we define liberty,
Goldwater's first sentence in effect chides us to pick, in a relevant
situation, the option that advances liberty the most. I believe that
much of a given philosophy is about radicalizing an idea, ideal, or
some claim of reality. Post structural/post modernism, for example,
relies a great deal on the truth that the meaning of symbols is
dependent on the context in which they are used. The implications of
this insight can be far reaching, but should it be the basis by which
we view all social reality? I don't think so and I find the whole
approach of radicalizing ideas, ideals, or truth claims to be mostly
counterproductive.
I have, in this blog, reviewed the
mental construct, natural rights, and have pointed out that that
construct holds liberty as a trump value. In its more extreme forms,
as in libertarian thought, the ideal, liberty, becomes radicalized.
In the extreme, the ideal takes on an antagonistic posture toward
other ideals such as civic virtue. This is true, not so much in
theoretical terms, but in practical terms. Richard Dagger provides
the following definition for liberalism – the more philosophic term
for natural rights – which is authored by Lance Banning: “…
[A] label most would use for a political philosophy that regards man
as possessed of inherent individual rights and the state as existing
to protect these rights, deriving its authority from consent … .”
1
Dagger goes on to describe civic virtue as follows: “Someone
exhibits civic virtue when he or she does what a citizen is supposed
to do.”2
How do these two ideals relate to each other? On the surface, I
think it is self evident that these ideals are relevant and important
to civics. But how they relate to each other is not so self evident.
In my presentation of these ideals
in earlier postings, I have expressed agreement with Dagger in that I
don't see the ideals as necessarily antagonistic to each other. They
are distinguishable from one another but not, in essence,
incompatible. There is a tension, though, between the two when one
of them is radicalized. This happens, for example, when liberty is
radicalized. If a person acts under a radicalized view of liberty,
there will be times, probably often, when practically unrestrained
behavior, even if limited by legal restraints, will lead to self
determined choices that have no concern for what is supposed to be
done. These behaviors will be aimed to advance self interests at the
expense of the common good and such acts, by any practical
consideration, do not constitute doing what one is supposed to do.
To express such a concern, as I am doing here, does not indicate that
one is anti liberty or anti civic virtue. The problem is in
the radicalization.
Let me review, before I expand on
how the two ideals can be at odds, on how the two not only can be
compatible, but also how they must be compatible. If for no other
reason, a necessary compatibility between the two lies in the reality
that no case exists in history – at least in modern history – in
which a complete disregard for liberty leads to a citizenry that can
be dedicated to the more noble aspiration to do what is supposed to
be done. Yes, there have been cases in which inspirational leaders
have established regimes in which liberty has been squelched, but the
duration of these regimes is limited. To some minimal degree, people
will only be concerned with what their behavior should be when each
person has a sense of liberty to decide what to do. Total coercion,
which is a total lack of liberty, might solicit obedience for a time
– in some cases, a long time – but the costs of maintaining the
means of coercion will finally become too high and forces, to
institute liberty, will find ways to express themselves. The most
recent expression of this generalization is the Arab Spring.
Under conditions of coercion, the
common good would not only be hard to find, but also hard to define.
Under such conditions, civic virtue will be in short supply in
everyday intercourse between citizens. As a matter of fact, to our
modern eyes, civic virtue will be expressed by actively revolting
against such coercion. In short, liberty is a social condition that
is part of the common good.
Again, I don't want to leave you
with the notion that the natural rights construct or traditional
liberalism radicalizes liberty. Only with adopting an extreme
version, such as becoming a libertarian, does one approach doing so.
Presently, libertarianism has, through the Tea Party, become
somewhat popular and is extensively covered on national TV and other
media. My concern is that such exposure helps to popularize
libertarian ideas, ideals, and reality claims. Further, I worry that
all of these mass media treatments, in a perverse way, will encourage
secondary students to accept more radicalized versions of natural
rights' views. I would hope that even if a civics educator does not
accept a more republican view, such as federation theory, to guide
his or her choices of course content, that such an educator would
become familiar with a more communal approach and use its concerns to
formulate appropriate classroom questions. These questions would be
designed to make the more extreme nature of what is being espoused by
radicals apparent. Whether or not a student accepts and adopts such
views is his or her prerogative, but such a choice should be based on
reasonable and responsible reflection on the implications such a
choice implies.
Teaching about conflicting ideals
is not easy. Part of immaturity is a lack of the ability to
appreciate subtlety and nuance. In teaching secondary students, a
teacher needs to be careful not to present ideas, ideals, and/or
claims of reality in such a way as to encourage students to
radicalize them. There is a natural tendency not only among
teenagers, but also people in general, to radicalize beliefs or
values. We easily divide reality into either-or perceptions. Good
or bad, goodness or evil, right or wrong, liberty or tyranny are just
a few of these “bi-polar” divisions. But reality is seldom so
easy, and this can definitely be said of realities relating to issues
that make up the subject of civics.
1Daggar,
R. (1997). Civic virtue: Rights, citizenship, and republican
liberalism. New York, NY:
Oxford. Quotation on p. 12.
2Ibid.,
p. 13.
No comments:
Post a Comment