This blog has dedicated itself to
describing and explaining a mental construct of governance and
politics – the liberated federalism construct. This construct is
presented as a guide in selecting the subject content for civics and
government education.
Through the postings of this blog,
I have developed what the tenets of this construct are. I have made
it clear that the construct presents a moral view. In doing so, it
is my responsibility to address how a moral perspective should be
presented in public school classrooms. As I have indicated in past
postings, to utilize a view of social reality that is based to some
degree on moral claims, one needs to justify such a choice. The
reason for this justification emanates from the reasonable concern
that such a choice can be seen as an attempt to propagandize a view
of politics to a captive audience. My argument to date has been
that, to some degree, any curriculum has to be built on some view of
not only reality, but also some conception of morality. Prevalent in
our public school classrooms today, I have argued, the prominent
construct guiding the choice of content in civics classes is what I
have called the natural rights construct. Within that construct, I
have pointed out that there is a moral outlook. A review of past
postings will provide you with the particulars of this view. Let me
just say here that it is impossible to present a civics curriculum
without taking a moral perspective. I will concede, though, that the
liberated federalism construct, the construct promoted in this blog,
has a more robust moral view. Despite this robustness, I firmly
believe that its use is not amenable to indoctrinating our secondary
students. This posting aims at explaining why this is so.
To address this concern, I believe
that one approach is to explain how liberated federalism treats the
relative importance and roles of values (central to moral
considerations) and facts. Their relation to each other has been a
subject, in one way or another, that has garnered the interest of
many philosophers. By reviewing what two philosophers had to say,
this posting will help explain why liberated federalism presents a
responsible way to address the moral concerns with which effective
citizens must deal.
Values and facts; how do they
relate? The philosopher, David Hume, made an extensive case for
forming a dualism between these two. To him, we cannot derive
values, what we believe to be good and, by contrast, what we believe
to be bad, from facts. Values cannot be reasoned. They are instead
the product of sentiment – our emotions. They are products of the
“gut.” Let us use an extreme case to illustrate the point: most
of us value life and, therefore, we find murder as immoral. Do we
believe this because the facts surrounding murder lead us to conclude
that murder is bad or immoral? Let's analyze this question.
One could cite the fact that
murder will not only hurt the victim, but also disrupt the lives of
that person's loved ones. Of course, murder, in terms of the victim,
deprives him or her of everything he/she has. These are facts. We
might say that murder disregards the value of human life and if left
unsanctioned, the results would be that such incidents would
generally increase the likelihood that any one of us could be
victimized. Our own lives might consequently be more in jeopardy.
These are conjectured truths or facts. Or one might simply state
that we are beings who empathize and that incidents of murder just
make us sad for those directly affected. Since we don't like being
sad, we should establish the conditions, such as policing and setting
up judicial courts, to arrest and punish murderers. All of these
conclusions are, at least in part, based on factual claims, but do
they lead us to valuing life and finding murder as immoral?
According to Hume – and many thinkers – the answer is no.
Hume argued that all of these
facts gain importance only because they relate to something we prize
emotionally – that is life, in general, or our individual lives,
specifically. All of these facts don't matter one bit unless we have
such a sentiment. In general, Hume argues that our knowledge of
facts is derived from experiences. He had a sporadic view of
experience. He saw our self-awareness as being the product of a
succession of experiences in which one experience did not have to
necessarily or in fact have much relation to other experiences. This
view has been described much like a movie in which each instance is
captured by a separate, individual exposure. We, for example, see
the facts that constitute ourselves (our ego) as changing constantly.
We are not in a meaningful way the person we were yesterday and we
will not be the same person tomorrow. The nature of this
“sporadic-ness” doesn't end with how we view ourselves. By
limiting what we can consider a fact – to those things we directly
experience – Hume argued that we cannot experience causes per
se, and so, therefore, we cannot reasonably attach a cause to any
effect – such as one billiard ball striking another and causing
the second ball to move. We make such connections because we want,
for practical reasons, a certain degree of predictability in the
world in which we live. We want to survive and to do so, we
believe recurring phenomena will continue to occur, just as the
chicken develops the habit of viewing the farmer who feeds it every
day as a welcome experience until the day the farmer wrings its neck.
Though the chicken cannot experience cause and effect, it apparently
makes such a connection of farmer-food due to the recurrence of the
farmer's daily appearance. The influence that such a recurrence has
is derived from the predisposition of the chicken to want to
eat and survive.1
The philosophy of John Dewey helps
us out here. His view points out that despite the fact that such a
sentiment for life is essential in establishing the immorality of
murder, facts are important in our attempts to analyze moral or
ethical questions generally or, in the case of murder, specifically.
Dewey was, in his writings, put off by dualism such as value/fact,
cause/effect, ends/means, body/mind. He agreed with Hume on the
notion that all knowledge is derived from experience. He was very
concerned, though, with a qualifier: experience has to be reflected
upon within the context in which it becomes known to us in order for
us to make sense of the experience. Dewey's view, as opposed to
Hume's sporadic view, is that experience has more of an on-going
quality whereas context is very important in giving meaning to any
phenomena we experience. In terms of cause and effect, for example,
Dewey writes about causes leading to effects and then effects being
new causes for other effects and so on. As one of the founders of
pragmatism, Dewey is very much into what works. While both Hume and
Dewey argue against absolute values or absolute morality, they both
arrive at such a claim from different origins. For Dewey, morality
exists in factual results. While Dewey didn't argue against the
bases of values or moral beliefs being sentiment, he seems to upgrade
the role of facts or experiences as being important in the
formulation of our values. For example, facts present us with
conditions that limit alternatives or fix outcomes, and this reality
has a great influence on which values we develop. As Philip Selznick
writes about Dewey's thinking: “… it is reasonable to say that
the norms are to that extent based on facts and even 'derived'
from facts. [On the other hand,] They may also, and at the same
time, reflect quite arbitrary interests and inclinations.”2
Of course “interests and
inclinations” are sentiments - things that we merely want. But
even with these sentiments, consequences of our value choices are
subject to inquiry - to factual realization. How our choices affect
our personal well-being and the social well-being around us are not
events occurring in our psyche, but are actual conditions in our
world.
By Hume saying that values are the
product of our “gut,” he implicitly delegates them to having an
arbitrary essence. They are subject to a behavioral mode of
development. More in line with Hume's thinking, we adopt values
through conditioning (reactions to rewards and punishments) and this,
in turn, is arbitrary. While this very well might be the case for
some individuals or for all individuals concerning certain values,
Dewey would claim that values can also be learned through
problem-solving and, as such, can be purposeful and not arbitrary.
He distinguished between “behavior” and “action.” Behavior
is derived from conditioned experiences – resulting from rewards
and punishments and little reflection – as opposed to action which
is derived from purposeful experiences in which students, through
cognitive awareness and reflection, actively seek those results that
are intrinsically self-rewarding and self-fulfilling.
The mental construct this blog
promotes, the liberated federalism construct, is based, to a great
degree, on Dewey's thoughts outlined above. It is a normative view
of governance and politics based on reflection. As such, the
construct would rely on presenting students with instructional
strategies that involve them in reflective activities. My personal
bias is to favor progressive strategies, but the use of the construct
does not preclude other types of strategies as long as whatever is
used does not exclusively count on students merely committing to
memory those facts, generalizations, and beliefs contained in the
content. The construct insists that students reflect on the
content, in an open manner, regardless of whether the material is
presented through problem-solving activities or taking lecture notes
or whatever else the instructor presents or has the students do.
1For
a delightful account of Hume's philosophy see Gaarder, J. (1991).
Sophie's world: A novel about the history of philosophy.
New York, NY: Berkley Books.
2Selznick,
P. (1992). The moral
commonwealth: Social theory and the promise of community.
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Citation on p, 21.
No comments:
Post a Comment