A
recurring theme of this blog has been the history of American
political thought and how it has shifted from one prominent view to
another – from what I have called the traditional federalist
perspective to the natural rights construct. Nothing illustrates
this more than the shifts in thinking by our jurists as expressed
through their court decisions. Of course, leading this change are
the constitutional decisions the US Supreme Court has rendered
concerning our basic rights. A number of postings ago, I reported on
how court decisions concerning religious freedom reflected this
shift. This posting will look at the jurisprudence concerning
speech.
Michael
J. Sandel1
provides us with a short account of that history. He points out
that, just as with religion, the overall view of the courts has been
toward prohibiting the government from restricting speech and
inhibiting government's ability to promote its version of the good.
Government might find constitutional reasons to regulate the
expression of speech – in regard to time, place, and/or manner –
but such regulation, generally, must not be based on the content;
that is, the state is to be neutral in any obstacles that it might
inflict upon the exercise of speech.
As
with all of the rights contained in the Bill of Rights, before
the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, the federal
government did not have any authority to protect citizens from any
affronts to those rights by the state governments. As far as federal
courts were concerned, states, such as New York or South Carolina,
could restrict speech, for example, as much as they wanted. The US
constitutional guarantee in the First Amendment was to protect
citizens against efforts by the central government. And even with
the one prominent situation in which the central government tried to
control speech – the enactment of the Sedition Act of 17982
– the law was never challenged before the Supreme Court. The main
challenge to that law came from two state sponsored resolutions –
the Virginia and Kentucky Resolutions – authored by James Madison
and Thomas Jefferson. These founding fathers' main complaint was not
that the law offended the individual rights of free speech or freedom
of the press, but that the law interfered with the states' right to
restrict speech and the press in the ways the law provided. So much
for any concern for individual rights among these founders. I will
add that the courts' concern for these rights didn't even cause a
ripple in the nation's federal jurisprudence until after World War I.
The
first serious judicial concern over legislative efforts to check free
speech came about as a result of the World War I laws, the Espionage
and Sedition Acts of 1917. An initial standard the court formulated
in the cases that emanated from the adjudication of individuals who
were found guilty of breaking these laws was the “clear and present
danger” standard. That is, a person's right to free expression
could only be held unlawful if the speech presented a situation in
which the speech would incite people to engage in disruptive and
dangerous activities in an immediate time frame. The speech, in
addition, had to have subversive content. And to demonstrate the
lack of judicial concern for these rights, it took until the late
1920s before the court overturned any of the convictions in these
“subversive” cases.
The
reluctance of the courts during the era of traditional federalist
thought to find favor with those who argued for free speech can be
demonstrated with a later developed standard: the “two-level
theory of free speech” standard. In a unanimous decision in the
Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire case, the court identified a level
of speech that did not have the protection of the First Amendment.
The Supreme Court decided in 1942 that speech found to be lewd and
obscene, profane, libelous, and/or insulting (“fighting” words) –
that is, speech that was in and of itself injurious or incited
immediate disruption – could be constitutionally restrained by law.
What seemed to be valued over individual freedom in this decision
was order and morality, not the principle of free speech. The
courts continued in this direction of limiting constitutionally
protected speech through the 1950s by adding commercial speech,
racial defamation speech, and obscenity as not being constitutionally
protected.
One
of the main criticisms of such rulings was that this two-level
approach placed the courts in a position to make very subjective
decisions. Trying to determine what speech was profane, for example,
called on judges to apply their personal sensitivities. These
criticisms increased in number and stridency until the court
abandoned the two-level approach in New York Times Co. v.
Sullivan. In this case, the court held against a libel decision
by ruling that any misrepresentation of the facts that was defamatory
had to be shown to be motivated by malice in order to be judged
libelous and not constitutionally protected. On another front
concerning free speech, Stanley v. Georgia held in 1969 that
an individual had the right to receive obscene materials. This
general trend in which the courts extended protections for speech –
in printed or verbal forms – continued through the 1980s. The
court established, with each decision, the principle that government
needed to be neutral in its perspective of what the good is in
determining what speech was acceptable or not.
Sandel
goes on to describe how the court has striven to establish ever more
neutrality standards by which to judge the constitutionality of
federal and local laws. No area probably has been given more
interest than political expression such as the burning of the
American flag as a form political protest, or what is considered
“hate speech.” But as we keep the overall trend in mind, what I
am emphasizing in this posting is that the trend has promoted a view
of governance which is neutral and, in turn, enables, if not
encourages, the individual to determine what values he or she will
strive to adopt – the essential position of the natural rights
construct.
With
the adoption of neutrality standards, the natural rights perspective
has been given a strong legal foundation. We are left free from any
collective sense of what the good should be. To what extent? The
courts have ruled against laws that prohibit the exhibition of
obscene movies at drive-in theaters where the images were visible
from nearby public streets. Maybe I am expressing old-fashioned
sensitivities, but to say such images do not express our cultural
sense of what is immoral, I believe, is a definite change in our
collective sense of what government should be allowed to control. In
a future posting, I will revisit this topic; the courts have wavered
some on this level of neutrality principle. But overall, I will
claim that the natural rights construct is well established by and
within our jurisprudence.
1Sandel,
M. J. (1996). Democracy's
discontent: America in search of a public philosophy.
Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
2A
law that made libelous speech against the federal government
illegal.
No comments:
Post a Comment