My
last posting addressed the difference between the traditional and the
modern and how that distinction affects reasoning within the
construct of federalism. I pointed out that within our national
history, a traditional form of federalism played a crucial role in
determining the essence of our political ethos. I also pointed out
that traditional thought and reasoning is concrete and unequivocal;
it commits to definite beliefs. Often the beliefs reflect religious
dogma. As such, traditional thought and reasoning lends itself to
clear visions of the good and it definitely tends to place priority
of a particular vision of the good over that of the right. By
“right” the reference is not to what is correct, but to what we
as humans have legitimate license to do.
I
have also made the argument in past postings that while initially the
mental construct that prevailed during the initial phases of our
political life was traditional federalism, the growing influence of a
modernistic construct grew in prevalence until, after World War II,
it became prominent. That construct I have named the natural rights
construct. As a modern view, the natural rights construct places the
emphasis on the right over the good. In a previous posting,
Neutrality and Speech,1
I trace the history of court decisions and how they reflect this
shift in terms of what is judged to be allowable speech. In this
posting, I want to take up that effort and look specifically at the
shifting view the courts have had on obscenity.
More
specifically, I want to address the uneasiness such a shift causes in
those who have to deal with the actual policies involved. Probably
no area of concern is more “touchy” in our culture than that of
sex. Within the Puritanical tradition of American culture, sex and
our handling of sexually explicit materials have had a telling
history. That history reflects, in stark contrast, the separate
phases of how our acceptance of sexual content has become ever more
liberalized.
According
to Michael Sandel,2
this liberalization has taken the following progression: first,
prohibition based on local standards of decency, then prohibition
based on tortured rationalizations in which thinly veiled concerns
for the good are proclaimed to be actually neutral concerns for
legitimate state interests such as safety and security and, finally,
tolerance of the dissemination and consumption of obscene material
with minimal restraints to protect the young or other sensitive zoned
localities. This whole shift is predicated on a commitment – a
commitment to the First Amendment right of free speech. But I
would submit that at its base is the issue over our ever increasing
concern for each of us to determine what values we, individually,
determine are correct for ourselves. Fortunately or unfortunately,
many of us value the consumption of speech that explicitly
illustrates sexual scenes and behavior better known as obscenity.
Whether this is good or not is difficult to determine under
modernistic reasoning. Under such reasoning, even to be considered
for legal prohibition, questionable material needs to be demonstrably
offensive or threatening to legitimate state interests. For example,
in response to the decisions which characterized the tortured
rationalization phase, current courts demand that any claim
associating the consumption of obscene materials to behaviors
affecting the safety or security of citizens needs to be supported
with empirical evidence. In such cases, commonsense arguments or
arguments based on sectarian precepts are not sufficient. If you
argue that obscene materials lead to a higher incidence of rape or
other sexual crimes, you have to provide the appropriate studies that
support the contention. A possible exception to this general
standard is the case of published obscene materials that depict
underage youths. In that case, the fact that children do not have a
legal standing that permits them to voluntarily submit to that kind
of exposure, even when and if parental permission is provided, does
indicate a bias toward a priori restraint. But even in that
case, I am sure that psychological studies can be readily supplied
that would indicate long term problems for those children so
exploited. Overall, the point is that any public policy prohibiting
the exercise of behavior protected by our identified and codified
rights needs to be justified by findings based on neutral ground and
supported by empirical study. Religious or other parochial beliefs
will not do.
Does
a call for a modern version of federalist thought and reasoning
abandon what its traditional version called for: a promotion of the
good? Here, an advocacy for federalism is challenged not so much
from a theoretical point of view, but from a political point of view.
How can any concern for the good in our public policy be acceptable
to a populace that has adopted a natural rights perspective? Such a
populace is readily disposed to see any government action promoting
its version of the good as an overreach into our private lives.
Whether government policy prohibits the production, dissemination,
and consumption of obscene materials falls under such a rubric.
First,
the purpose here is not to outline a propaganda program for our
public schools. The purpose is to advocate a social philosophy or
theory that can provide a foundation for a civics curriculum.
Second, as such, a philosophy or theory need not outline a set of
beliefs that students are called upon to accept, but it provides a
view of politics and government upon which an educator can base
instructional questions – exactly what the natural rights construct
does for most contemporary civics instruction today. Third, to the
extent that federation theory has a moral commitment, those who
utilize the theory should not be shy about expressing to students
what that commitment is. This should be done not as espousing the
truth, but as providing a choice which reflects the view of the
majority and can be criticized as to its appropriateness and
functionality. Neither should governmental jurisdictions be shy in
expressing what the collective sense of the moral is. Expression can
and should fall short of prohibitions when such stands come in
conflict with protected rights. But such expressions should be clear
and direct. Here, the use of proclamations and resolutions can be
the vehicles by which such collective judgments can be expressed.
And what is the moral standard for such judgments? As I have argued
in this blog, my view of what a liberated federalism morality should
be is a commitment toward the promotion of societal welfare – with
the trump values of societal survival and the advancement of a
society's goal and aims (a value that presupposes a normative
judgment by the collective).
So
how do obscene materials fit or relate to this theorizing or
moralizing? In terms of instructional strategy, concern over the
advancement of a society's goals and aims brings a focus on the
communal quality of that society. Why? Because to reach those goals
and aims, social capital is demonstrably important. Robert Putnam3
writes of social capital; he defines social capital as a societal
quality characterized by having an active, public-spirited citizenry,
egalitarian political relations, and a social environment of trust
and cooperation. The instructional question would be: does the
publication, dissemination, and consumption of obscene materials
diminish the levels of social capital in a society? This is a
legitimate question to ask high school students – maybe even middle
school students. How does the right of free speech relate to this
trade? Is this – the preemption of legislation that prohibits
obscenity – what our first national congress meant when the right
was added to our constitution or when the authors and ratifiers of
the Fourteenth Amendment extended basic rights protections
against state governments? Many such questions can be studied in
appropriate classroom settings.
So,
the point is that federation theory does not need to abandon its
concern for the good. It does, though, need to take on a more modern
approach; that is, an approach that shifts away from either
propagandizing a set of concrete values, as was the case with the
traditional, or a complete abandonment of treating moral questions in
the classroom, as has been the case under the natural rights
curriculum. More specifically, the use of federation theory needs to
be open to incorporate both scientific research and non- dogmatic
moral analysis.
1Posting
for April 8, 2013.
2Sandel,
M. J. (1996). Democracy's
discontent: America in search of a public philosophy.
Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
3Putnam,
R. D. (2000). Bowling alone:
The collapse and revival of American community. New York:
Simon and Schuster.
No comments:
Post a Comment