In
this blog, I have presented the attributes of a federalist polity. I
have emphasized the communal aspects of such an arrangement. Those
include the commitment to a central fraternal ethos, a genuine
concern for fellow citizens, and a shared responsibility toward
building and enhancing social capital. This posting is dedicated to
what a federalist polity is not. Specifically, it addresses the
utopian notion that a federal union is one in which there is no
competition or the potential for greed. In this posting, I want to
leave you, the reader, with a clear understanding that to advocate
for federalism does not mean one believes it is possible to set up a
political entity that is devoid of greed and self- serving behavior.
On the contrary, a lot of the structural arrangement that are derived
from federalist principles is so structured to meet the very human
tendencies which act contrary to the aims of federalism, but is very
much a part of the human condition. Therefore, federalists recognize
the presence of both the very human potential for citizens to have
genuine concern for the fate of others, especially for those in whom
they are federated, and of selfish motivations.
So
where are we as Americans when it comes to these apparently opposite
drives or proclivities? Some politicians like to banter about the
notion that American politics is above having clashes between our
economic classes. Attempts to advance policy geared toward enhancing
equality are labeled by these partisans as acts of class warfare.
And the question arises: if we are all federated under the
Constitution of this republic, aren't we beyond pitting the
interests of one income group against that of another? Of one region
against that of another? Of one age group, religion, ethnicity
against that of another? How does one go about addressing these
concerns? Are there points of conflict between these groups that are
just part of the human condition that need to be accommodated or
regulated?
History
is clear on this point: to date, ever since humans have hit upon the
ability of civilizing themselves, there have been among them people
of varying degrees of economic well-being. That while civilizing has
permitted the overall ability to increase wealth, not all have shared
in that bounty equally or anything near it. This posting is
dedicated to addressing what this fact means to the makeup of a
polity – even our own.
To
begin with, varying levels of economic well-being reflect one form or
another of competition. Considered indispensable in the creation of
wealth, this competition is engaged between those who have a lot and
those who don't have a lot. But it is also engaged between those who
comprise the rich – rich versus the rich – and between those who
comprise the not so rich – the not so rich versus the not so rich.
The competition takes on the form defined by the ground rules that
prevail in a given economy: there are capitalist rules, socialist
rules, aristocratic rules, and so forth. There can be many different
sources of competition in a society – some economic, some not.
Probably most fundamental, though, in defining the nature of a
society, is the competition over economic assets within a society.
And several basic factors prevail in all economic systems: the need
to motivate the producers of economic wealth, the need to compensate
the workers, the need to distribute sufficient exchange resources in
order to generate sufficient demand, the need to be efficient in the
production processes, and so on.
Much
of the study of economics analyzes these factors. But there is also
a political angle to all of this. Because the competition over this
distribution involves high stakes, the rules of the economic game are
very important and those rules are established by the political
institution of a society. That process of rule making begins with
developing and implementing a constitution, the basic law of the
land. And while it is not the only concern constitution developers
address, it is one of their essential and central concerns. And once
a basic constitution for a society is hammered out, in order to
maintain its legitimacy, a polity is well served in preserving its
workable formula with appropriate policy and in describing and
explaining to its populace how and why the instrument addresses the
essential factors in the fashion that it does. Of course, if the
formula does not work or worked once but now ceases to do so, current
politicians need to be about working out a new political arrangement
– amending the old constitution or creating a new one.
We,
the United States, have the oldest written constitution (not all
constitutions are written). By and large, there is real support for
it and we more or less abide by it. Actually, we abide by it quite
faithfully. And so our civic instruction should be about describing
and explaining to its populace, particularly its younger members, how
and why we go about addressing the essential factors in the manner
our constitution does. There is an array of ways to do that. One
such way is to revisit the thinking of our founding fathers and see
how they saw these universal factors and any other factors that
swayed their thinking about the relation between the classes and
other competing groups. Richard Hofstadter does just that in his
book, The American Tradition.1
Let me summarize what this historian sees were the assumptions and
claims of the founding fathers:
- There is a human nature that humans do not grow out of or have the ability to give up.
- This human nature is both universal in any given time and across all times – that is, it is the same always and in all places.
- This human nature has, as a central attribute, an insatiable drive that manifests itself within each of us to further self-interests.
- Self-interest can be instrumental in encouraging individuals to join with others who share the same interests or nearly the same interests to form what James Madison called factions – what we might call interest groups.
- Depending on the governing system in place and other environmental factors, self-interest can motivate licit or illicit behavior, productive or destructive actions.
- Attempts to convince individuals or factions to abandon their self-interest are bound to fail because such attempts defy an unchangeable human nature.
- Any interest group or faction that gains unfettered control of the government or the economic system of an area will take advantage and exploit all other interests, individuals, or factions – that is, they will become oppressive.
- The only way to avoid such oppression is to devise and implement a system of governance that pits faction against faction, interest against interest, vice against vice, or more germane to our concern here, class against class. This arrangement checks the ability of any one faction from gaining an oppressive advantage.
These
founders were federalist politicians; three of them described and
explained these beliefs in a set of arguments that were compiled in a
volume entitled The Federalist Papers. The purpose of those
arguments was to sell the new federalist constitution of 1787 in
order that it be ratified. The term that is used to describe the
thrust of these beliefs is a “balanced constitution” that the
founders believed summarized what their handiwork attempted to be.
It is balanced in its aim not to allow any faction or class to have a
level of power in which it can dictate policy which threatens
unreasonably and destructively the interests of other groups. In
short, the aim is to avoid oppression.
A
polity that is so organized should issue policy that substantively
protects the opposing aims of opposing factions within its
jurisdiction. It should be on guard against those developments that
upset the balance. For example, it should be wary of any one group
or set of groups becoming so rich that they can parlay that wealth
into unchecked political power. On the other hand, it should not
issue policy so daunting to human effort that individuals of the
various classes become convinced that effort and hard work are not
sufficiently rewarded and, as a consequence, allow disincentives of
not only hard work, but innovation. It should serve to encourage
conservation of our resources of all types – psychological,
environmental, social, artistic, and the like. These are but a few
of the concerns policy makers have to keep in mind so as to keep in
balance the competition that is so important in advancing societal
welfare.
Calls
for balanced constitutions date back to antiquity, but a federated
formula in the US added a level of sophistication that premiered with
the American experiment. The deed to check and counterbalance forces
could not be successful by merely including all factions within the
political arrangement of the nation; it had to be arranged in such a
way in which all the above concerns could be satisfied. Hofstadter
identifies several elements in our constitution that have been, to
date, sufficiently successful in addressing these concerns. They
are: one, our constitution has divided power with each class having
control over one or another of the structural elements – we have a
legislature, for example, with one house representing the wealthy
(the Senate) and one the masses (the House of Representatives); two,
the constitution provides for an officer who represents all the
people, executes policy, and is further empowered with a veto – and
even this latter power can be overridden by an overwhelming majority
in the legislature; three, the maintenance of local jurisdictions,
under the state authority, prevents national interests running
roughshod over local interests; four, at the same time, the national
jurisdiction is big enough to prohibit any one faction from
dominating the nation; and five, there is an independent judiciary,
without access to armed resources, that oversees the process by
authoritatively judging whether all parties – both public and
private – are operating within the rules and, in addition,
determines what the rules mean. And let me add to Hofstadter's list
of balancing forces: all of these provisions make it very difficult
for the government to accomplish anything without significant demand
from the citizenry. In terms of protecting against oppressive
government, nothing protects more effectively than a government that
finds it difficult to devise and implement policy.
Of
course, before its implementation, all of this was an ideal – a
theory that had been formulated to meet the realistic self-interest
of human beings and allow for a people to go about and strive toward
more communal ambitions. By accommodating those necessary functions
that lead to societal welfare, it is a formula or model that permits
and perhaps encourages a mode of governance that allows the citizenry
to pursue lives worth living over the long haul.
But
heaven was not created in 1787. Perfection was not attained. There
is another side. The other side is what happens when, as a result of
being so balanced and hampered, the government can't respond
sufficiently, in either terms of substance or time, to the needs of a
constituency? What happens when, despite all of these structural
elements or because of them, some group or faction does gain control
and is able to become oppressive? That has, some might say, happened
or nearly happened. In the Gilded Age, large corporations had
enormous power and were able to render all other factions nearly
impotent. Yet a reform era – the Progressive Era – did come
about and addressed the most egregious conditions of that time. This
effort included several amendments to our constitution. Some
suggest that we are again nearing those conditions. If so, how will
we respond? If so, is the problem one of deficient policies or is it
one of systemic shortcomings? If the latter, have the deficiencies
come about because times have changed and our constitution no longer
functions sufficiently well? These are the questions of our time.
They are serious and highly consequential to the welfare of our
people and of the world. Our students need to be aware of what we
are facing and it helps immeasurably if they at least know and
understand from where we came in terms of structure, aims, and
theory.
1Hofstadter,
R. (1948). The American political tradition.
New York, NY: Vintage Books.
No comments:
Post a Comment