I
have from time to time in this blog used the expression: the freedom
to do what one should do, not necessarily what one wants to do. I
have further associated this expression with the vision of liberty
promoted by federalist thought – at least as an ideal for which
federalists strive. I have also made the claim that the founding
generation of our political system – those patriots we recognize as
starting our republic – were swayed, more so than by any other
construct, by federalist thought. Therefore, one can readily assume
that I see the founders believing in a severe socialization of youth
in which they are taught that the good of the community trumps the
good of the individual. By so doing, we can solve the Rousseauean
problem: “… we no longer have citizens.”1
Or stated another way, the founders argued: we should all conduct
our lives in such a way that we place the interests of the community
above our own. That is what it means to “do what we should do
...”.
The
nation, during its Puritanical beginnings and for many years
thereafter, placed this kind of burden on individuals. The earliest
settlers might not have taken this notion as far as Rousseau did, but
religiously stern discipline characterized many of the expectations
of those New England settlers. In this blog, I have traced the
history of how the harsh initial conditions of the frontier demanded
this kind of discipline to assure the very survival of the early
settlements. But naturally, as those conditions softened, the
rationale for such a view became ever more difficult to maintain.
Slowly, the more hospitable environment – caused in no small
measure by the discipline exerted by the earlier Americans – led to
political and social perspectives that liberalized our laws, customs,
mores, and ethos. In addition, writers other than Rousseau, such as
John Stuart Mill and John Locke, presented arguments that individuals
are entitled to rights and that the community cannot and should not
impose burdens on individuals that transgress those rights. These
rights are provided by nature.
Since
prior postings have spelled out this development, my purpose here is
to merely remind you of this overall evolution and to point out that
by the time of the founders of our present republic, there was still
a very strong sense of societal duty and obligation, but that this
sense had been somewhat compromised – how compromised is up to
interpretation and debate. Read what a current scholar believes
about the state of mind most founders were in by the late eighteenth
century:
[The
Federalist – collection of essays promoting the newly written
constitution of 1787] presumed … that man is selfish and his
politics factious. Moreover, stability of the regime is assured only
through “mechanical devices” aimed at pitting “ambition against
ambition” within government and faction against faction in society.
…
It
can no longer be taken for granted, however, that the American
constitutional founders – even the authors of The Federalist
– can be described as Lockean liberals. … I will argue that the
revisionists were right in asserting that the constitutional founders
were more civic-minded, more concerned about the dispositions of
citizens to undertake public duties, than the “possessive
individualist” … I reject what I see as a tendency in the
revisionist literature [though] to assume that where civic virtue is
discussed – and practiced – liberalism must be absent.2
In
other words, it is hard to peg the founders on a continuum from
republicanism – with a commitment to civic duty – and liberalism
– with a commitment to individual interests. My take is that the
difficulty lies in the nature of the transition the nation was only
beginning to experience at that time and is still progressing today.3
One
thing we should not forget when considering the founders is that they
saw themselves creating a layered polity. A problem they were trying
to solve was how do you get citizens to take on the burdens of
obligations and duties without the resulting regime being oppressive.
How do you, at the same time, maintain within each of us the
ambition to help build that great nation with a vibrant economy that
not only provides a better material life, but provides the resources
to make the nation strong in relation to other nations? How do you
create the conditions that would lead to a foreign policy
sufficiently vibrant to protect our national interests? The national
layer of the polity was to set the political infrastructure by which
such a posture could be created. It would set about a governmental
framework to allow this more ambitious agenda by allowing people, at
least as far as the national government was concerned, to advance
their individual goals and aims. It would create those conditions
that would allow a national market with a free trading zone to be
established and unleash the natural ambitions of Americans to not
only prosper on the Atlantic seaboard, but to conquer a continent
chock full of resources. With these aims eventually accomplished,
they believed that prominence, power, and wealth would naturally
follow. Allegiance to this more grandiose government would be based
on its protection of individual rights by first limiting its powers
to those delegated in the national compact and later by adding a set
of rights spelled out in the Bill of Rights. On the other
hand, as far as promoting what Richard C. Sinopoli calls “a
sentiment of allegiance,” the local government, under the auspices
of the state governments, would take the lead in this more communal
ambition.
Why?
Because the national government was, in the eyes of the founders,
probably too big and represented too many diverse interests to be
able to engender the attachment and allegiance upon which civic
virtue depends. Smaller entities, like the states, with more limited
populations, interests, and diversity can engender those bonds of
attachment the founders believed essential. Of course, what exactly
was viewed as deserving allegiance would be, from state to state,
very different and, of course, in one area this diversity almost led
to the union dissolving. As it was, it led to a bloody civil war.
Where
are we today given this tension between the interests of the
individual and the interests of the community? A lot of politics
today is an expression of this tension. If anything, the alternative
views between the two are being expressed with more intensity than
what had been the case some thirty years ago. The presidency of
Ronald Reagan gave a shot in the arm to those views promoting the
individualist side of the debate. Recently, those who champion the
duty and obligation side have had some successes. For example, the
passing of the Affordable Health Care Act has been interpreted by
many as the society taking on the responsibility of providing health
insurance to many who can't afford it. This provision, in turn, is
viewed as a program that will lead to a healthier nation and, as
such, promotes the common good. The final outcome of Obamacare will
go a long way in defining where we are: are we tilting toward the
“me” or are we tilting toward the “us”? Are we finding
morality under a doctrine of individual determination or under a
doctrine of societal welfare calculation?
1Quoted
in Sinopoli,
R. C. (1992). The
foundations of American citizenship: Liberalism, the constitution,
and civic virtue.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press, p. 3.
2Sinopoli,
R. C. (1992). The foundations of American citizenship:
Liberalism, the constitution, and civic virtue.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press, pp. 4-5.
3In
terms of the prominent views of those in the political class between
the writing of the Declaration of Independence
and the US Constitution,
I am partial to the description provided to us by Gordon S.
Wood. See Wood, G. S. (1998). The
creation of the American republic 1776-1787. New York:
W. W. Norton and Company. This seminal work was originally
published in 1969.
No comments:
Post a Comment