One recurring message of this blog
is the distinction between the natural rights view of liberty and
that of the liberated federalism view. At the risk of sounding
repetitive, I summarize the difference with the following comparison:
the natural rights view states that liberty means a person has the
right to choose his/her course of action as long as the choice does
not hurt someone else or deprive someone else of the same
prerogative. On the other hand, for the liberated federalist
position, the view of liberty lies in the right of the person to do
what the person believes he/she should do; that is, the right to be a
moral person. Given that even the most selfish and self-centered
person tends to believe he/she is not immoral, then what does it mean
to believe in having the right to do what one should do? What, in
practical terms, distinguishes what one wants to do from the right
thing to do?
This is a more complicated
question than it appears to be. To answer, one needs to delve into
moral theory. To begin with, and this is a topic I have previously
addressed, one assumes that individuals truly have the ability to
make such choices – that we truly have free will. I will not
address this prerequisite condition here, but assume that, yes, for
practical purposes, we do have free will or enough of a free will to
make our question over the right thing to do worth asking. I will
begin addressing the “right thing to do” question here by
reviewing some basic ideas associated with moral thinking.
Let us start with the connection
between values and morals. While morals have to do with the good,
what we value is simply those things we want in the form of things or
conditions either now or in the future. We can judge prior
conditions according to our values, but we can't change what has
already happened. So, from the perspective of determining behavior –
the “to do” part of our concern – we are interested in how
values affect us in the present or in the future. Yes, we can value
that which is immoral. Few, though, actually see what they value as
immoral; we have the ability to rationalize our choices to convince
others and ourselves that what we want is moral. But alas, just
look around; what people rationalize as good is often not moral. So,
given the possibility that our values are not moral, if we strive to
be moral, we need to analyze our values in an objective fashion. It
helps to garner the opinions of others, especially those who do not
have an interest in what we are reviewing, and listen to what they
think of our choices. That's why I like the ethics column in the New
York Times Magazine – I recommend it. As for this posting,
let's look at some basic ideas concerning values.
Maurice P. Hunt and Lawrence E.
Metcalf1
(later in Byron G. Massialas and Jack Zevin2),
identify three types of value assertions. Let me present them in the
following three statements:
- A person likes something (P likes X) because that something leads to or acquires something else or provides a state of being. This line of thinking is judged to be rational.
- P likes X because that something is entailed in something else, such as a philosophy, an ideology, or a religious belief. While one might question the rationality of the “something else,” the value in question, “X,” is also considered a rational choice.
- P likes X because P simply likes X. This is judged to be irrational.
Let me comment on each of these.
Briefly, the first of these ways of valuing is considered utilitarian
in nature. A person likes or does something because it will lead to
a goal or object he/she cherishes. For example, this might take the
form of a student valuing his/her attendance at college because the
education the student is receiving will lead to a degree and, in
time, to a better job, higher pay, higher levels of work
satisfaction. At least, those are goals that education can
facilitate. In the second statement, the person seeks, ultimately,
an association between what is valued and, to some predetermined
sense of goodness, an ideal or a set of ideals. These philosophic,
ideological, or religious ideals are non-empirical in nature. For
example, a person likes his/her neighbor because the person is a
member of a religion that holds such sentiments as moral (or not
having them as immoral) and, as such, an emotional state one should
hold. Both the first and second statements are considered logical
systems in that they relate to some consequence. Behaving in
accordance with the resulting value position leads to something,
something that is desired. But the third statement is something
else.
The third statement is illogical
for it has no reason for existence except for its implied bias. For
example, why does a person favor vanilla ice cream? He/she does so
for no particular reason; the person just does. For an educator who
is trying to deal with some controversial issue in discussion, a
student who utters such a value statement and can't provide a reason
should not be uncontested when such a value leads to social
conditions that affect others. For example, if the question arises
of who should win the upcoming election and the student says Jones
but cannot give a reason, that student should be further pushed to
come up with a reason. After all, the winner of an elected position
will have a role in determining public policy that will affect many
other citizens. But if the assertion does not affect others, then
the student's comment need not be challenged. We all have our
irrational preferences. I do like vanilla ice cream – especially
with a little Grand Marnier poured over it – but when it comes to
Wendy's Frosties, I'll go for the chocolate.
But I digress. The thing is that
different social studies theorists have favored one approach to
valuing over the other. In my next posting, I will briefly review
two of them. For this posting, I want a review of these approaches
to valuing so that we might come to a better sense of what it means
to “do what one should do.” There is no greater responsibility a
civics teacher has than to get his/her students to seriously question
their motives about their social actions. In choosing a liberated
federalist view to guide a teacher's strategies in the classroom, the
teacher is taking a more proactive approach than that encouraged by
the natural rights view. By leaving it up to the individual to
decide what is moral without at least some reflection, is simply
unjustified and irresponsible. My contention is that under a natural
rights regime, the effort to get this sort of reflection is simply
too muddled and undirected. It leads to instruction that is too apt
to be without any guidance whatsoever. To pursue such instruction is
at best naïve and at worst abandoning one's responsibilities. On
the other hand, liberated federalism has guidance baked into its
elements – most notably, in its professed value hierarchy.3
1Hunt,
M. P. and Metcalf, L. E. (1968). Teaching
high school social studies: Problems in reflective thinking and
social understanding. New York: Harper and Row,
Publishers.
2Massialas,
B. G. and Zevin, J. (1967). Creative encounters in the
classroom: Teaching and learning through discovery.
New York, NY: John Wiley and Sons, Inc.
3I
have written extensively in this blog of a proposed moral code I
developed. See, for example, posting, Implementing Federalist
Moral Code in the Classroom,
December 16, 2011. The proposed moral code is based on federalist
ideas and ideals.
No comments:
Post a Comment