With this posting, I conclude describing and explaining the
five disciplines I deem to be essential in productive argumentation –
productive, that is, along federalist values.
To sum up: I have borrowed from
Philip Selznick’s[1]
“five pillars of reason” to devise this set of disciplines. My intent is to encourage educators – and
other interested parties – to see argumentation from two perspectives: one, the typical view of argumentation as a
means of convincing others of a point of view; and two, as a process that can
be used to seek the truth. These
disciplines, when combined with relevant skills, can be utilized in classroom
instruction as a means of having students conduct inquiries over issues,
especially if those issues are spurred by concern over federalism.[2] To date, the disciplines reviewed have been
order, principle, experience, and prudence.
This posting will look at dialogue.
When considering prudence, one point highlighted was the
concern over the ends of arguments; that is, when considering a contested point
of policy or view, one should be cognizant of the ends the argued means are
meant to target. Oftentimes, ends seem
to be assumed; many times, those assumptions differ in that the ends they
represent differ. We can often detect
these variances by the language each side uses.
For example, in the debate over abortion, one side will use terminology
that speaks of the killing of babies.
The other side does not counter this reference directly; instead it will
speak of a woman’s right to control her body.
Neither side directly contradicts the other’s claim because such
language gets to the ends of the argument.
The anti-abortion side has as its unstated ends its desire to please a
deity. The other sees this battle as one
prong in the war for women’s equality.
Instead of getting into all that, argument tends to avoid such “messy” aspects
and just assumes, in its arguments that its ends are above reproach.
But it is here that participants should argue and they should
do so through dialogue. We engage in
such dialogue not necessarily to secure agreement. We engage in this process to seek truth by
seeing other perspectives, other trains of logic, and other instances of devout
and honest commitment. It humanizes
those with whom we disagree and it does so not by avoiding strenuous debate and
passionate exchanges but by engaging in them.
That is part of it: the passion,
the emotions, and the rhetoric. And yet,
we can do all of this with civility. But
civility presupposes a general environment of basic trust that those with whom
we disagree are honest, generally moral, and pursuant of the common good. Therefore, we can’t have dialogue – not of
the type described here – with everyone.
As a matter of fact, dialogue, while it can be attempted in usual
argumentation, will probably occur infrequently. Why?
We don’t live in a society in which federalist values are generally seen
as ideal. But this does not preclude us
from holding them collectively – or even individually – as an ideal that we can
strive toward. And so, one so disposed,
can seek dialogue, attempt it, and engage in it whenever possible.
But even if dialogue were readily experienced, this does not
mean such argumentation will lead to agreement.
Some opposing ends have been with us since the beginnings of civilized
life, if not before. It would lead,
though, to greater understanding, empathy, and respect among us all.
Although the risks are real, there is
a place for the prophetic spirit, for passion and rhetoric, in communicative
inquiry. Without confrontation, unspoken
assumptions may never be truly exposed to criticism and debate. People may not really listen.[3]
And what of the demands of the classroom? How does this dialogue work there? The classroom can prove to be a very
demanding area. First, students are a
captive audience. What is presented to
them is mostly not of their choosing. A
process that relies to any degree on argumentation, much less the process I am
suggesting, needs to be cautiously approached.
Arguments over ends – what is usually treated as assumed contentions –
will come to a screeching halt if the appropriate build up is not laid
out. Premature attempts at such
arguments can easily devolve into shouting matches. If that happens, those who will cease to
listen will be the students who are sitting before the teacher who is
attempting to promote such dialogue.
[1]
Selznick, P.
(1992). The moral commonwealth: Social
theory and the promise of community.
Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
[2]
For those new to this blog, the blog is, in
part, dedicated to promoting a mental construct in the guidance of curricular
content in the subject matter of civics.
That mental construct I entitle federation theory. The accompanying remarks introducing the
postings of this blog gives the reader an overall description of what federation
theory is.
[3]
Ibid., p. 62.
No comments:
Post a Comment