This new development with Cuba has led me to consider some
thoughts about moral thinking. Those who
are opposing the establishment of diplomatic relations with the island nation
cite the human rights abuses the Castro government has been guilty of for so
many years. These have included,
according to our government, the killing of dissidents, the intolerance of
dissent, the expropriation of private property, the jailing of those who have
acted against the regime, and the list goes on.
Whether the extent of these abuses is as draconian as those opposing the
Castro government would have us believe is open for debate. I am sure that a great deal of it is
true. The opponents of recognizing the
Cuban government couch their opposition in moral terms – good enough.
Those who have argued in favor of reestablishing relations
seem to base their position on several factors, not the least being that
relations were suspended back in January, 1961, fifty-four years ago. A lot has happened in those years. We have established relations with other
“sinful” regimes; China and Vietnam come to mind. And yet the policy toward Cuba has remained
and has included a strict embargo against trading with that communist nation. The goal, ostensibly, has been to cause
enough pain and weakness in Cuba so that the Castro brothers would be forced to
change their policies or be overthrown.
It has not worked. Even the
opponents of the new policy argue that that regime is as oppressive as
ever. So the Obama administration says: let’s try a new way; let’s establish
relations; trade with them and try to influence them into making the desired changes. That’s their argument. So I ask:
is it immoral to deal with such a regime? For conservatives, this is quite a difficult
question.
Earlier in this blog, I reviewed the difference between
thinking about moral questions from a categorical approach versus a utilitarian
approach. To quickly review that
difference: categorical approaches see
moral positions as fairly uncompromising.
Acts are either moral or immoral by the mere fact that they abide by a
moral value or they transgress a moral value.
In order to determine the morality of a value, a question is asked of
it: what would happen if everyone behaved
in accordance with the value; could a society sustain such behavior? For example, what if you valued lying? If everyone lied, there would be no trust and
a society would not be sustainable.
Therefore, lying is immoral and any value that supported it would be
immoral. On the other hand, truth
telling, as a value or a behavior, does not threaten a society and, therefore,
is moral. Once this type of review is
made of any value and its resulting behavior, one can determine which values and
behaviors are moral.
Utilitarian reasoning is quite different. With this approach, the question is one in
which a person calculates how many people find a behavior and its corresponding
value useful. That is, does the behavior
accrue some result which a person wants?
A moral choice is one that provides more usefulness than what’s
otherwise available. For example, if
choice X satisfies 51% of the population and choice Y satisfies 49%, then
choice X is the moral choice. Each
person is free to determine what constitutes usefulness or satisfaction for him
or herself. As can be seen, this
approach is significantly different from the categorical approach.
Now let’s apply this to Cuba.
I believe the Cuban situation provides us with an interesting
dilemma. Categorically, a believer in
democratic values would tend to see any relations with a dictatorial regime as
immoral. The policies of the Castro
government have been immoral by the standards democrats hold. Now, of course, this becomes a bit complex;
one needs to justify democratic values, but that’s not my aim in this
posting. Let us just accept the morality
of democratic values. Conservatives,
those who might oppose opening relations with Cuba, might take the posture, and
many do, that this change in US policy is immoral. But a central problem with categorical thinking
is its tendency to not compromise. There
are times, though, when moral values come into conflict. While conservatives might hold uncompromising
democratic values, they also might very well value profits. After all, profits provide the necessary motivation
for us to engage in entrepreneurial activities.
Without those activities, democratic societies cannot function, since
they count on individuals to freely decide to engage in economic activities. By doing so, they create the goods and
services people need and want and also the employment that provides the wages
used to buy those goods and services.
The only other option is to abandon democratic values and structures and
force people to engage in economic activity – the very type of policy many
conservatives accuse the Castro government of enforcing.
With opening relations with China and Vietnam, we opened markets. Conservatives of the more libertarian
persuasion might see such actions as providing more usefulness than a
categorical posture that would disallow such relations. With more markets, business activity
increases and more people will benefit and that goes for people in all of the
countries involved. Conservatives who
rely on a more utilitarian moral view will tend to favor opening relations and
would probably extend such reasoning to Cuban relations. As I said above, this turn in Cuban relations
provide us with an interesting dilemma for many, but especially for
conservatives.
No comments:
Post a Comment