A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, August 18, 2017

THE DISCIPLINE OF REFLECTED ARGUMENT (pt. 3)

To date, this blog has reviewed three qualities or disciplines which characterize responsible argumentation.  The three are order, principle, and experience.  This posting will explain the remaining qualities offered by the social scientist, Philip Selznick.[1]  They are prudence and dialogue.
Prudence -  A shorten explanation for prudence is:  this discipline calls on a person to demand a critical review of any derived theories or models against ongoing experience.  It is what Selznick calls “practical wisdom” and while reason is end-centered, it favors the continuum of means and ends as when one looks beyond rules to the reasons for those rules.
If one is about formulating a legitimate, moral argument, that process, by its very nature, is one that seeks the truth.  When one starts the process without prejudging the result, has emotions under check, and is about searching the facts through experience, then one is looking for what is real. 
This process can also be one in which legitimate efforts at persuasion are attempted.  Therefore, there is a dual-purpose process in which one can pursue one or both aims: truth ascertainment and/or persuasion.  As earlier indicated, to be honest and effective, there are disciplines or concerns that the process should effectuate.  These concerns provide important context when considering prudence.
A person practices prudence in two domains.  One domain is the disposition to distinguish between rules as abstract ideals and their practical application in real situations.  The other is keeping moral aims targeted when pursuing policy which is often the product of argumentation.
Imprudent behavior occurs when one blindly imposes a rule in a way that disregards all the conditions a situation presents and applies the rule in a mechanical way.  Such imprudence forgets the reason(s) for the rule in question.
By looking at the purpose of a rule, and its value premises, judges make good their commitments to principled decision; by examining particular circumstances they take account of the inescapable uniqueness of human situations.  This is not a retreat from reason but a distinct mode of deliberation.[2]
For a rule to work, they must account for the issues involved within the situation(s) in which the rule is to be applied. 
A problem with ideologues and detached bureaucrats – in many cases – is this lack of prudence that leads to ineffective policy implementation and judicial tyranny.  A common experience by most is when a citizen deals with a bureaucrat either in government or some large corporation.  Blind rule-following often wrecks the purposes of the rules unnecessarily and leads to a loss of citizen or customer support for governmental or business practices.
The other domain follows this more practical claim.  It simply points out that in considering means and ends in the content of an argument, one should coalesce the two.  In a morally based argument, means and ends can be mutually supportive in that both are true to moral standards.  These, in turn, need to be transparent and defensible by submitting and explaining, when requested, these standards to moral critique. 
This blog has offered the federalist moral standards.  When so informed, one can judge how effective the advocate of an argument is in exercising the discipline of prudence.  For example, if a tax policy is geared to encourage increased economic activity by lowering costs of business, but loses sight of maintaining sufficient demand levels by consumers or potential consumers, the initial means-ends connection has disregarded the function of the first end to be the means to a more encompassing, desired end – a healthier economy for all.
And that leads to the last discipline,   
Dialogue – A shorten description is as follows:  This discipline calls for a person to honor diversity of ends in terms of both goals and understandings held by others.  This honor is acted upon by engaging with others in mutual efforts by honest agents toward seeking truth and/or prudent policy.  As such, it depends on a level of social capital or, at least, a proactive commitment to seek or establish social capital.[3]
Earlier, when considering prudence, one of its attributes highlights a concern over the ends of arguments; that is, when considering a contested point of policy or view, one should be cognizant of the “ends” the argued “means” are meant to target.  Oftentimes, ends, especially ultimate ends, seem to be assumed; many times, those assumptions differ in that they reflect differing or opposing ends. 
One can often detect these variances by the language each side uses.  For example, in the debate over abortion, one side will use terminology that speaks of the killing of “unborn babies.”  The other side does not counter this reference directly; instead it will speak of a woman’s right to control her body.  Neither side directly contradicts the other’s claim because such language gets to the ends of the argument. 
The anti-abortion side has, as its unstated ends, its desire to please a deity in that they hold the religious belief the fetus (there is no such thing as an unborn baby) has a soul.  The other sees this battle as one prong in the war for women’s equality.  Instead of getting into all that, argument tends to avoid such “messy” aspects and just assumes, in its arguments that its ends are above reproach.
But it is here that participants should argue and they should do so through dialogue.  One engages in such dialogue not necessarily to secure agreement.  Instead, one engages in this process to seek truth by seeing other perspectives, other trains of logic, and other instances of devout and honest commitment. 
It humanizes those with whom one disagrees and it does so not by avoiding strenuous debate and passionate exchanges, but by engaging in them.  That is part of it:  the passion, the emotions, and the rhetoric.  And yet, one can do all of this with civility.  But civility presupposes a general environment of basic trust; i.e., that those with whom one disagrees are honest, generally moral, and are pursuant of the common good.
Therefore, one can’t have dialogue – not of the type described here – with everyone.  As a matter of fact, dialogue, while it can be attempted in usual argumentation, will probably occur infrequently.  Why?  Because, the nation is not currently a society in which federalist values are generally seen as the ideal, much less an ideal by which people behave.  Instead, it has become a society in which self-interest has become predominant and the arbiter of what is ideal.
But this does not preclude a people from holding them collectively to some degree – or even individually – as an ideal that can be strived toward.  And so, one so disposed, can seek dialogue, attempt it, and engage in it whenever possible.  Federation theory is proposed as a way (or better stated, as part of a way) to seek a more general adoption of views supportive of the common good.
But even if dialogue were readily experienced, this does not mean such argumentation will lead to agreement.  Some opposing ends have been with societies since the beginnings of civilized life, if not before.  It would lead, though, to greater understanding, empathy, and respect among a population.
Although the risks are real, there is a place for the prophetic spirit, for passion and rhetoric, in communicative inquiry.  Without confrontation, unspoken assumptions may never be truly exposed to criticism and debate.  People may not really listen.[4]
And what of the demands of the classroom?  How does this dialogue work there?  The classroom can prove to be a very demanding place.  To begin with, students are a captive audience.  What is presented to them is mostly not of their choosing.  A process that relies to any degree on argumentation, much less the process suggested here, needs to be cautiously approached. 
Arguments over ends – what is usually treated as assumed contentions – will come to a screeching halt if the appropriate build-up is not laid out.  Premature attempts at such arguments can easily devolve into shouting matches.  If that happens, those who will also cease to listen will be the students who are sitting before the teacher and attempting to engage in such dialogue.
That completes a review of Selznick’s disciplines.  Beginning with the next posting, this blog will attempt to meld these disciplines with Stephen Toulmin’s model for logical argumentation.  In general, the aim should be to apply each of the disciplines outlined to date to each of the elements of Toulmin’s model.



[1] Philip Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth:  Social Theory and the Promise of Community (Berkeley, CA:  University of California Press, 1992).

[2] Philip Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth:  Social Theory and the Promise of Community, 60-61.

[3] Robert Putnam tells us that social capital means having an active, public-spirited citizenry, egalitarian political relations, and a social environment of trust and cooperation.  See Robert D. Putnam, “Bowling Alone:  America's Declining Social Capital,” Journal of Democracy, January, pp. 65-78.

[4] Philip Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth:  Social Theory and the Promise of Community, 62.

No comments:

Post a Comment