There is probably no more
contentious issue a teacher can bring up in class than the issue of abortion
rights. This writer can personally
attest to the emotions this issue can surface in the classroom. Should it be avoided due to this reaction on
the part of students or is there a way to handle it? And by handling it, can a teacher have
students discuss the elements of it including how the issue relates to
federalist values with the order Philip Selznick identifies as a “pillar of reason?”[1]
Of course, this federalist concern is what makes these
questions relevant to this blog. So, any
treatment of it should first point out how the issue is a federalist one. There is more than one concern along these
lines, but here, in this posting, one will be emphasized. That is, this issue either reflects harm that
can be done to a person’s sense of dignity and integrity or, more central, to
his/her right to life. Either way, this
issue involves very central federalist values.
And a lot of this issue revolves around definitions, the definition of
life, of personhood, and of rights.
This
posting targets the bi-categorization of what is at stake. Does an abortion deny life generally or does
it deny life to a person? The
“right-to-life” proponents – that is, those against abortion rights – claim
that an abortion is tantamount to murder.
It extinguishes life from a human being.
The right-to-choose people – that is, those that argue a woman should
have the right to determine what happens to her body – claim that an embryo or
a fetus, to various gradations, is not a person.
This
last claim needs a bit more clarity.
That is, according to the claims of the right-to-choose camp, a human
entity must be mature enough as a fetus or must be born to be a legal person – “person”
is the term the Constitution uses to designate a human entity worthy of
recognition in terms of rights. This all
sounds very legalistic and devoid of the humanity involved. But when one speaks of rights, especially
when the rights of parties are in conflict, that’s what tends to happen.
This
posting will not take a stand on the issue.
The purpose of the blog is avoid doing so when the question cannot be comfortably
settled by classifying it clearly as being a federalist related issue or
problem. As the above definitional ideas
demonstrate, one can be pro-federalist on either side of the issue and, in
effect, the parties do not agree as to the federalist stakes involved.
Therefore,
using this issue in the classroom should make this factor clear and well-known. What this posting seeks to provide are facts
that affect how one views this issue and, in turn, how it affects the quality
of federalist rule.
The
first fact this writer feels is relevant is a portion of the First Amendment to
the US Constitution. It reads, “Congress
shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion …” It immediately goes on to state “… or prohibiting
the free exercise thereof …” But it is
the first phrase that seems to be relevant.
How can a government “establish” a religion? Can it do so by legislating a religion’s
moral precepts?
Some
think yes, while some disagree. Those
who disagree cite the role religions play in expressing culturally accepted
moral precepts that people believe law should advance. In terms of the latter role, for example, surely
religions state murder is immoral.
Should that not be considered by lawmakers when considering banning
murder?
In
Reynolds v. United States, 1879, the Supreme Court upheld a federal law
banning bigamy (another behavior generally believed to be immoral), but the
decision was not clear as to whether the decision was based on a religious
rationale. That Court more than hinted
that such a law had enough secular consideration behind it to legitimately ban
bigamy and therefore its rationale is not limited to a purely religious belief.[2]
Subsequent
cases listed by the Bill of Rights Institute show a clear recurring theme; law
cannot be dictated by religious precepts or religious interests – they cannot
also hinder people from believing or abiding by religious precepts assuming
those beliefs do not counter constitutionally legitimate laws.[3] Either way, laws seem to need secular
reasoned rationales to pass constitutional muster, especially when they
prohibit citizens from pursuing their life’s choices.
So,
how does this relate to the abortion issue?
The question for a class, therefore, would be: is a woman seeking an abortion aiming to
commit an act that is or should be illegal?
And, is the terms of the illegality sufficiently secular, as opposed to sectarian,
or, by being so central to traditional religious beliefs (seen as a form of
“murder”), does this behavior constitute an exception to the general
determination of the courts? Is it the
belief that upon conception, the embryo is given a soul by God and, therefore, is
a full-fledged person?
Another
line of inquiry that is relevant has to do with the right-to-choose
argument. Those who argue this position
seem to be relying on certain aspects of the gestation process an embryo or
fetus undergoes. For if the ultimate
concern is whether one is dealing with the rights of a person – minus any
religious claims – then it seems reasonable that the test is how closely that
entity – an embryo or a fetus – takes on the attributes of a person during
gestation and when do they happen?
In
this, David Brooks provides useful information.[4] He reports:
at the fetus stage, a fetus grows 250,000 brain cells a minute and by
birth has 20 billion brain cells. He/she
develops early in the fetus stage taste buds which can recognize sweetness and
garlicky flavors from mother’s latest meal.
The fetus, at five months (out of nine) will begin to withdraw from
pain. By the third trimester, the fetus’
eye movement indicates he/she is probably dreaming during sleep. It isn’t until the third trimester that
he/she indicates any consciousness even of his/herself.
“Herold
[the name Brooks gives his exampled case] spent nine months in the womb,
growing and developing, and then one fine day, he was born. This wasn’t a particularly important event as
far as his cognitive development was concerned, though he had a much better
view.”[5] Of course, gestation is noted for a whole
slew of developments, some being extremely complex. But what teachers should ask students
is: if being a person is the criterion,
as the right-to-choose people argue, then of these developments, which are most
relevant to the concern over whether a fetus is a person?
The
Supreme Court has answered that question with the determination that at the
third trimester of gestation, the fetus has unqualified right to be considered
a person. Extreme measures – such as the
endangerment of the mother’s life – need to be in place for that fetus’ life to
be legally terminated. But a one-month
fetus or even a five-month fetus is not considered enough of a person to be
granted unquestioned rights of a person.
Is this a correct standard or the application of a correct standard?
Some
argue that not even a fetus of any age should be granted those rights. What do students think, if they can get pass
the religious standard to consider such a question? But even religious people should consider
this question because it helps them know and understand where the
right-to-choose people are coming from.
Similarly,
the right-to-choose people should know and understand the reasoning of the
right-to-life people. Even if it is
difficult, given the importance of the issue, helping students to do this –
either way – falls within the responsibility of civics instruction. At least, it seems to this writer, that is
the case for any civics teacher that accepts federation theory to guide his or her
efforts.
[1]
Philip
Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth: Social Theory and the Promise of Community
(Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press, 1992).
[2] “Religious Liberty: Landmark Supreme Court Cases,” Bill of
Rights Institute, n.d., accessed November 7, 2019, https://billofrightsinstitute.org/cases/
. One should note that this was a
federal law, not a state law which usually legislates over police power issues;
i.e., laws protecting the welfare, safety, justice, morals, order, and health
of state’s citizenry.
[3] Ibid.
[4] David Brooks, The Social Animal: The Hidden Sources of Love, Character, and Achievement
(New York, NY: Random House, 2011).
[5] Ibid., 31.
No comments:
Post a Comment