Yes, a cheesy title,
but in its way, it hits the point of this posting. This blog, after rendering a cursory
description of how Romanticism got started in Europe, now begins describing its
introduction into the US. And in that,
one comes across familiar titles: “The
Legend of Sleepy Hollow” by Washington Irving along with his “Rip Van Winkle.” There’s James Fenimore Cooper’s The Last
of the Mohicans and the depiction of Puritanical morals in Nathaniel
Hawthorne’s The Scarlet Letter and Herman Melville’s Moby-Dick.
But of direct interest
to this blog are the essays and other non-fiction works of Henry David Thoreau
and Ralph Waldo Emerson. And with these
efforts, one can see that many Americans readily took up the themes their European
counterparts had been expounding. That
included a high dose of moral judgement, an emphasis on individualism – from a
more psychological perspective – and the importance of intuition, more on this
in a bit.
They also promoted an
almost reverence for nature – especially in the case of Thoreau – in which the
message was it was “naturally” good while society was indulgent and corrupt. Of course, as the last posting described and
explained, these themes were recurring in Romantic offerings in Europe as those
artists and writers took aim at the Enlightenment’s reliance on reason. And to underline this divorce from
Enlightened thought, American Romantics hit upon a term that they felt emboldened
their disdain, that being transcendentalism.
Why? That question takes one back to Europe. There, the origin of this anti-reason strain gets
an initial upstart not from an anti-reason argument, but one that placed
certain restraints found in the works of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke. In their works – to use a Lockean term – the mind
at birth was a tabula rasa, a blank slate.
It, then through
experience, perhaps resulting from the succession of rewards and costs that one
encounters, one “learns” to see those things that one should pursue and what
one should avoid among what all those encounters teach a person. In that one learns, from observing how one’s
mind works, to reason since reasoning increases the probability of success. To that argument, Immanuel Kant sought to
qualify it.
He did not argue that
reason and the ability to reason were not important aspects of learning and
decision-making, but he claimed there was more going on in the mind and those processes
of sorts were inborn abilities. And that
needs to be explained. To begin, yes, at
birth one experiences and/or observes isolated things out in one’s surroundings,
but that is all a subject can do that relates to his/her reasoning ability.
That is, each encounter
is merely observing a sensation. At that
stage, reason could not do anything with each sensation or, to use the jargon, each
thing-in-itself. As such, each is phenomenal,
or datum and one cannot pass any judgement about it. To this point, there is agreement with David Hume
in that Hume’s skepticism questioned the human ability to draw any conclusions
even if colliding billiard balls then move away from each other.
But, Kant adds, that
upon that pure information, one has built-in a mental capacity – not based on
experience – that allows one to make judgements of what underlies or constitutes
those experiences. And that is what Kant
called with the unfortunate term, noumenal (roughly pronounced new-ou-min-al).
This noumenal is a
totally different realm of knowledge into which the mind can tap. It is through this element that the mind can
investigate the nature of things or to pass judgement as to its ultimate truthfulness,
its functionality, its morality, and other qualities that transcend its
physical qualities, i.e., beyond one’s observation of the things-in-themselves. And here, according to Kant, one does not use
reason – reason only deals in the phenomenal.[1]
All of this review
reminds this blogger of what he reads concerning contemporary psychological
study of these human, mental abilities and processes. For example, Nobel prize winner, Daniel Kahneman,
writes:
Our everyday intuitive abilities are no less marvelous than
the striking insights of an experienced firefighter or physician – only more
common …
[quoting Herbert Simon] “The situation has provided a cue;
this cue has given the expert access to information stored in memory, and the
information provides the answer.
Intuition is nothing more and nothing less than recognition.” …
An important
advance is that emotion now looms much larger in our understanding of intuitive
judgements and choices than it did in the past.
[An] executive’s decision would today be described as an example of the
affect heuristic, where judgements and decisions are guided directly by
feelings of liking and disliking, with little deliberation or reasoning.[2]
All this gets heavier as
one plunges into Kant, and the purpose here is not to do so – even if this
writer could – but to give the reader a sense of why Romantic Americans adopted
the term transcendentalism. In doing so,
they probably extended Kant’s purposes, but it did fit into what they wished to
promote. As with their European
counterparts, they had an attitude against reason and Kant’s transcendent
argument fit their designs. Allen Guelzo
explains:
There were, Kant said, two things which amazed him – the starry
heavens above, which were phenomenal, and the moral law within which belonged
to the noumenal. Never the twain would
meet, at least methodologically.
Philosophy could not become transcendent. But, through the gift of the noumenal, it
could become transcendental. Reason, and
all of its limitations, half heartedness, and sterility, could retire off the
stage and minds could rejoice in knowing the certainty of external phenomena
and the intuition of transcendental wonder.[3]
And wonder seems to be
what many Americans were searching to find in the 1820s and 1830s.
As with the Great Awakening,
the first signs of this transcending that is Transcendentalism appears in the
Boston area. It devolved from Unitarianism,
a Protestant sect springing from the days of the Great Awakening, on the
Harvard campus. By the early 1800s, it
had become the most prominent religion in the Boston area.
Upon the election of
Henry Ware as a professor of divinity as early as 1805 and the ascension of John
Thornton Kirkland as president of that college in 1810, a certain natural
evolution from Unitarian beliefs took hold, an outgrowth or sort of rebellious thinking
that promoted free consciousness and initially valued intellectual reasoning.
But this view moved on
and began to question such Unitarian biases of mildness, sobriety, and cool
rationalism. They, the self-anointed Transcendentalists,
sought more intensity. Parallel to otherwise Unitarian beliefs, they went
looking for more visceral spirituality in their beliefs and in the religious experiences
that they encountered.[4]
These notions took root and led to the
eventual founding of the Transcendental Club in Cambridge in 1836 under the
leadership of George Putnam, Ralph Waldo Emerson, and Frederick Henry Hedge.
The club had female
members and of note, Thoreau was also a member.
It published a journal, The Dial.
But the club and its movement did not enjoy widespread influence during the
1840s. As a matter of fact, it did not
hit its stride until later in the mid-nineteenth century. At that time, Transcendentalism influenced a
growing movement known as the “Mental Sciences.” Later, it took on the name “New Thought.” It considered Emerson its intellectual father
as well as depending on a long list of influential British writers of those
years.[5]
It turns out that these
Americans had little direct exposure to European Romantics and most of what
they understood or knew of them came to them through the works of Thomas
Carlyle and Samuel Taylor Coleridge. It
is through their presentation of Romantic ideas that this blog will next look
at and report on their influence.
[1] Henry E. Allison, “Kant, Immanuel,” in The Oxford
Companion to Philosophy, edited by Ted Honderich (New York: Oxford University Press, 1995), 435-438.
[2] Daniel Kahneman, Thinking, Fast and Slow, (New York,
NY: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2011),
11-12.
[3]
Allen C. Guelzo, The American Mind, Part II
– a transcript book – (Chantilly, VA: The
Teaching Company/The Great Courses, 2005), 23-24.
[4] Ian Frederick, “The Emergence of Transcendentalism,” American
Studies at The University of Virginia, University of Virginia (November 2014),
accessed September 13, 2021, Rise of
Transcendentalism (virginia.edu) .
[5] “New Thought,” MSN Encarta, Microsoft (November
11, 2002), accessed September 13, 2021, New
Thought - MSN Encarta (archive.org) .
No comments:
Post a Comment