Liberated federalism, the
view that this blog promotes to guide curricular strategies in civics
education, has as one of its elements the idea of communal democracy. In turn, communal democracy is distinguishable
from what the dominant view of today is.
That is the natural rights view, which promotes a democracy that is
based on an electorate of individuals as opposed to a reflection of a
community. In this area of concern,
Philip Selznick offers significant insights.[1]
In most day-to-day life,
there is not much difference between the two perceptions, but over the long
haul, the differences are significant. For
example, individualistic views rely on governance and administration of policy,
both from the public and private sectors, to be bureaucratic. The communal view strives, where possible, to
rely on people-to-people services and orientation. The US has come to accommodate the
bureaucratic approach. A more federated
mode of administration would shift people’s expectations to the latter approach.
That is, a post bureaucratic response to social demands and
ills is central to a communal democracy.
It calls for policies by government that are sensitive to community
resources and to their needs. These are
judgments that sense and accommodate the fact that communities differ, but that
all of them need human interactions, not cold calculations of cost-benefit
analyses.
A classic bureaucratic solution to a social problem area
was the decision to put urban police officers in patrol cars and to eliminate
the neighborhood police officer. Another
example, the proposal of vouchers for school choice, also infuses the cold
calculations of a market to meet the human, community problems associated with
education. These examples are only two
in the “sea” of systemic solutions which make sense utilizing marginal analysis
but are inefficient when measured by holistic community standards and by real
human needs to interact with real people.
Central to the federalist view is the intervening role of
associations between the individual and the state. These associations include such basic
institutions as families and churches.
The aspect of communal democracy on which this reliance is based is on
what Selznick calls political pluralism.
Here, the aim is to disperse power by allocating to these associations a
certain level of autonomy. The quality
of democracy is enriched by the texture of its elements as expressed within the
commonwealth and that these associations provide.
They add a source of identity, provide a training ground
for leadership, act to discourage impulsive actions, and function as a
restraint on government. “Federalism is
the keynote, and the federated unities are major groups – religious,
educational, economic, cultural, ethnic, political. In this view, the effective participants
in the political community are associations, not individuals.”[2]
In the model this blog will present in a future posting,
this view of effectiveness will play a central role. But a word of warning is called for – albeit
reluctantly: As an aspect of communal
democracy, this view can also be used as a justification for collectivist
solutions. Unfortunately, fascist or
communist models can also employ this same rationale to bolster their claims
and prescriptions to remedy perceived social maladies.
In guarding against such applications, personhood must
never be sacrificed for the aims and tactics of any association – be it
political, social, and/or economic. This
does not preclude socialist policies but limits their vibrancy or encompassing
provisions. Association or organization
is seen as a method, not an end, of individual welfare.
In another area of
concern, even under the auspices of a liberated federalist approach, communal
democracy as an attribute of an association should not be employed to justify a
status quo that entrenches the privileges of the elite class. The nature of associations tends to protect
their own internal, existing power distribution arrangements. Therefore, the principles of a communal
democracy need to be applied to policies that govern these associations, as in
labor laws that regulate the internal activities of unions.
And one might ask: with so much being placed on people being
communal, does this leaning leave one unprepared for the actions of factions? James Madison defines factions as “… a number
of citizens, whether amounting to a majority or minority of the whole, who are
united and actuated by some common impulse of passion, or of interest, adverse
to the rights of other citizens, or to the permanent and aggregate interests of
the community.”[3]
First of note is Madison’s concern for the
“aggregate interests of the community.”
That betrays the founder’s ultimate concern and his federated leanings. But beyond that, he reveals between what
Selznick calls democratic pluralism and oppositional pluralism. Somewhat in counter position to democratic
pluralism is oppositional pluralism.
This Madisonian principle calls for the
conflict between associations and factions to be the bulwark against arbitrary
and authoritarian government. This civil
antagonism acts as a preventor of any single or oligopolistic – where the few
rule – control of the government in which the interests of the general welfare
would be sacrificed.
Madison
did not foresee the concentration of economic and political power that has
ensued in the American arena.[4] Selznick labels this Madisonian view as
liberal pluralism or oppositional pluralism.
In this arrangement, the government is to find the equilibrium among
these factions.
But irrespective of what the national or commonwealth
interest might be, such concerns pose a threat to a federated polity and are
enhanced by the existing concentration of economic power. That is where a strong cultural, federated
base is essential – a common belief in federated values. And there lies an important role for civics
education.
Added
to this concentration of power and wealth, America has also experienced the
pluralization of its cultural base. The
Madison view was written under a significantly more, assumed homogeneous
population.[5] So, what one can say and be aware of is that the
nation, demographically, has gone through significant changes and if for no
other reason, earlier views of federalism need to be changed accordingly. Adopting a vigorous view of democracy, one that
is in tune with the nation’s population, is prudent if not necessary.
With
that consideration, communal democracy respects the minority’s value to
cultural membership – however that might be defined during a given period. It would find coercive assimilation unhealthy
to its principles and would proceed to avoid it, if not prohibit it. On the other hand, it would similarly look
with displeasure at any cultural subgrouping that coerced its members into
maintaining any person’s membership in a culturally based association.[6]
The
only insistence this view would hold, according to this blogger, would be that
culturally, any messaging and other language orientating communication within
the populous, if relevant, be in support of the nation’s constitutional
principles (of which there is an array of foreign cultural beliefs that do not fall
in line with such principles).
Any other type of substantive messaging is open
to how individuals wish to adopt and accept their personal relationship with
any cultural preferences they might hold.
And with this disposition among Americans, it promises – as it has done
so to this time – make life in this nation more interesting and enriching. This posting will end with this note, but the
next will continue in the vein.
[1] Philip Selznick, The
Moral Commonwealth: Social Theory and
the Promise of Community (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press, 1992).
[2] Ibid., 518, emphasis added.
[3] James Madison, “The Advantages of Union,” in Great
American Thinkers Volume I: Creating
America from Settlement to Mass Democracy, edited by Bernard E. Brown (New
York, NY: Avon Books, 1983), 218-252,
220.
[4] For example, Stacey Vanek Smith and Cardiff Garcia,
“Companies Get Political,” NPR/WFSU (January 13, 2021), accessed July 1,
2023, https://www.npr.org/2021/01/13/956553990/companies-get-political#:~:text=Companies%20Get%20Political&text=They%20donate%20billions%20of%20dollars,aloof%20from%20the%20political%20scrum AND Robert L. Heilbroner and Lester C. Thurow,
Economics Explained: Everything You Need
to Know about How the Economy Works and Where It’s Going (New York, NY: Simon and Schuster Inc., 1982).
[5] At least as expressed by John Jay. See John Jay, “Concerning Dangers from
Foreign Force and Influence [Federalist Paper, 2],” in The Federalist Papers
(New York, NY: Signet, 2003), 31-35.
[6] Most commentary on this topic has been on forces in
society that discourage or insist on abandoning cultural traditional beliefs or
customs from foreign cultures. Yet back
in the late 1990s, Michael Walzer wrote of this bit of pressure in reverse,
i.e., of foreign groups enforcing cultural modes to be insistent upon by
immigrants. See Michael Walzer, On
Toleration (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1997).
No comments:
Post a Comment