A teacher facing a class and
charged with instructing students about the governance and politics
of their nation has a somewhat unique responsibility not faced by
other teachers. Sure, in some way or other, all teachers have unique
aspects regarding their subject matter and their duty to teach it.
But in this posting, I want to relate what I find unique about
teaching civics and government. I believe that when the job is to
teach about these areas, a teacher is dealing with a subject that
begins and ends with moral issues. In between there are other types
of issues – resource availability and distribution, power
arrangements, egos, histories of relationships, and the like – but
in the end it's about “who gets what, when, and how,” as Harold
Lasswell pointed out, and who should get what, when, and how
as Daniel Elazar pointed out. These questions can literally be about
life and death, or they can be about progressing toward or away from
ideal states when the ideal is a reflection of values, mores,
customs, and varying degrees of thought-out theories concerning life
both at the individual and societal levels. The teacher faces a
group of youngsters who already have embedded within them prejudices
and dispositions even before the teacher begins a lesson. In most
cases, the outlooks they hold are not even consciously recognized,
but are the innermost springboards for how they will respond or react
to words or images that the teacher will present to them.
Recent work of cognitive
scientists has been shedding light on how these mental recesses
function not just for secondary students, but for adults as well.
One cognitive scientist is George Lakoff. In this posting, I want to
share one the fundamental insights he establishes in his book, Moral
Politics, and apply it to the challenge our teacher faces every
time he or she introduces a new topic.
Suppose I, as a civics teacher,
begin a lesson by asking the following: should an emergency room at
a nearby hospital provide medical care to a person brought in with a
serious medical condition but who has no means to pay for the care?
Some students will readily agree that care should be given and
express their surprise that I would even ask such a question. For
those students, it's just common sense that such treatment should be
forthcoming to a person so in need. Others will probably say “of
course not” and again ask why I would ask such a question. Their
take is that if you need to “purchase” a good or service you
should be ready, willing, and able to pay for it. Yet, while others
will simply say they don't know, for many of the students who do
“know” it's just a matter of common sense. While I don't know
what the distribution would be in a given class among those
expressing the different possible answers, I was always taken with
how many students see their responses as merely expressing the
obvious and not be able to appreciate the complexity of such a
situation. Yet, even when seen as common sense by many in the class,
the fact that not all agree begs the question: so, how common is
this sense?
This situation poses the following
concern for a teacher who doesn't want to simply impose a “right”
answer to the question of whether treatment should be given to the
indigent patient. The teacher must probe the situation in such a way
as to not turn off either the students who “know” the patient
should be given treatment or the students who “know” that the
patient should not be given the treatment. Lakoff addresses this
seemingly troubling challenge. He writes:
One of the most fundamental
results in cognitive science, one that comes from the study of
commonsense reasoning, is that most of our thought is unconscious –
not unconscious in the Freudian sense of being repressed, but
unconscious simply in that we are not aware of it.1
In order to visualize these
unobservable mental operations, Lakoff has conceptualized two
categories of such unconscious systems of basic inclinations that go
into forming the content of our “common sense.” The two
categories are metaphorical common sense and radical categories.
Metaphorical common sense operates
when we unconsciously see some type of reality in such a way that we
are susceptible to accepting a certain language of reference. That
is, the language refers to the reality in question – the case of
the indigent patient, for example – as exemplifying some other
simpler reality that is similar enough to stand in as an organizing
vision for that which is less understood. For example, if in my
question above, a student is inclined to believe that the above
patient should get the needed treatment, a narrative could be one
relating the incident to a child needing help from a parent. Such a
student might argue that like that child, the government, the proxy
parent, makes it illegal to turn away such a patient. The metaphor
of a family with parents making sure the children – citizens –
are taken care of, at least as far as providing essential things in
life such as health care, is quite common in our political
literature. On the other hand, a student who argues against the help
might use a related image of tough love parents. These parents are
willing to administer the harsh lessons of life that teach the
would-be patient and others that there is no such thing as a “free
lunch” in this world. By doing otherwise, the government or the
hospital would be subordinating irresponsibility.
Both use, as often is the case
when alluding to government, the metaphor of a family to devise
explanatory narratives that reflect deep seated biases. One possible
metaphor is that of a nurturing parent in this family arrangement.
Such a bias would probably favor providing assistance for our
indigent patient. The other version or bias, the one that would deny
the treatment, could possibly rely on a strict parent metaphor. Such
students would be concerned with the precedent such treatment would
set and make it more likely that others would learn that one needs
not worry about being indigent when it comes to health care.
Again, the other category of
unconscious biases is what Lakoff calls radical categories. Radical
categories refer to those tendencies people have in wanting to cast
others, who have certain similarities among them, with certain
characteristics which are not justified given the facts relating to
those so categorized. Lakoff identifies a list of radical category
types or prototypes. I won't list them here – get a hold of the
book for his complete review – but one of them, to give you a sense
of what Lakoff is referring to, is “typical case prototype.” In
this type, all members of a group share characteristics unless
otherwise distinguished. If someone is described as an American, the
bias might be to visualize a white male Protestant. If I said a
bird, a common bias is to think of a feathered flying creature the
size of a robin or cardinal. In discussion, these biases can and
often do conjure up images of reality that can easily be misleading
or they can betray or be instrumental in formulating conscious
beliefs that are over-generalizations – a primary source of
prejudices.
The danger is that in a discussion
about our needy patient, a teacher unaware of the varying biases
which lead to unfounded conclusions about the situation can find it
difficult to discern the unconscious mental origins of the thoughts
students express. If a teacher is so disadvantaged, he or she might
find it difficult to question the student in such a way as to solicit
appropriate introspection. The student, if challenged ineffectually,
might simply dig in his/her heels and not entertain any further
considerations. Such an interaction between teacher and student can
easily end in frustration for the teacher – the purpose of the
lesson not being met – and a student who might feel a range of
emotional reactions that are counterproductive. These might be the
sense of being picked on because he or she doesn't share the
teacher's opinion or self- righteousness for standing up for what is
obviously true, in the student's eyes, against the authority of the
teacher.
This posting is meant to simply
present this area of concern. I hope to address it further in the
future. But let me conclude this take on this problem area by
pointing out again that I believe this concern is somewhat unique to
civics and government teachers – at least to the degree it pertains
to current societal issues that are very much confronting the
nation's citizens on a daily basis. Not only is confronting these
unconscious biases germane to civics' discussions, but the biases
also pose hurdles to teachers which are highly varied and possibly
intense in a given classroom.
1Lakoff,
G. (2002). Moral politics: How
liberals and conservatives think.
Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press. Quotation on p. 4.
No comments:
Post a Comment