A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, July 21, 2017

SOCIAL IMPLICATION OF REGULATED CONDITION

This posting is a continuation of the previous posting.  If the reader missed the last posting, he/she is encouraged to click on to it and get the context of this posting.  Overall, this and the previous entry looks at regulated condition, a form of equality.  The purpose is to see how a liberated federalist model is “activated” and depict how an association, particularly a government, meets a political challenge.
Social Implication – A commonwealth is faced with a double-edged sword.  On the one hand, the inevitable ranking of individuals leads to an uneven distribution of material values.  Such a reality, though, threatens the level of moral equality in the commonwealth – especially if the unevenness is extreme or functions to prohibit others from such advantages. 
Ranking is not only pervasive among societies of all kinds – even among those who set out to abolish such rankings – but it is also readily justified within those societies either directly or through some rationalization.  Calls to end all uneven distributions are unrealistic and attempts will cause unacceptable costs to other values.[1] 
In other words, policies that seek equal results, as is called for by critical theory, would be too costly in terms, not only in funding any resulting programs that seeks to accomplish such equality, but also in other ways as well.  History shows that attempts to even out distributions act to squelch the motivation of those who would otherwise engage in hard, creative work which results in advanced technological and other production oriented activities. 
Selznick points out that the experiences of collectivist societies which have made such attempts to end all uneven distributions have failed miserably due to talent flight or disengagement.  This seems to indicate that such motivation would be squelched.[2]
The key to resolving the tension between equal results and regulated condition is the classic liberal call for equal opportunity.  Selznick describes this value:
No one should be hampered, no door should be closed to anyone, because of a prejudice against that person’s social origins.  Whatever opportunities exist should be open to all without regard to social class or (as later extended) to race, creed, ethnicity, or gender.  Thus equality of opportunity has the limited objective of overcoming prejudice while maintaining the legitimacy of differential rewards.[3]
In short, the focus is on ending any caste elements within the commonwealth.  Affirmative action – proactive government policy that aims at eliminating arbitrary inequality – under a value of moral equality, is limited to certain activities.  They are:
·        identifying and providing appropriate training to those victimized by discrimination;
·        helping members of a discriminated group, or, if efforts are made to assist such victims, demanding evidence that public or private agencies providing such assistance have done so in good faith and have exerted a meaningful effort to rectify past incidents of discrimination by showing actual accomplishments toward those ends that advance federalist equality.
What about those who have not been discriminated against but find themselves unequally treated due to their lack of success in securing financial or material resources?  Selznick calls for helpful efforts be extended to them also because by doing so it would upgrade the group – the collective.  That is, the whole commonwealth is negatively affected by the reality associated with persistent poverty.
Public agencies, such as schools, should provide resources to poorer members of the commonwealth to encourage recipients to be able to compete for the limited material values.  This aim encompasses two ends:  directed assistance to provide the basic requirements of life (food, shelter, etc.) and access to the educational resources that are available to improve the competitive status of the disadvantaged.
The commonwealth would be based on the meritocracy that allows those who produce or have good fortune to benefit from their efforts or luck, but it dismisses as illegitimate the ideal that holds that “winners” are inherently superior.  Inequalities in such a value system – one based on merit – are tolerated because to eliminate them would be costly and impractical and would be disruptive and counterproductive to the general creation of wealth in terms of material and other assets.
Chronic inequality that renders segments of the citizenry to poverty ultimately works to the disinterest of all, including not only the disadvantaged and the discriminated, but the advantaged as well.  Therefore, the moral equality that is sought is based on a reciprocal advantage, not on sympathy, pity, or benevolence.  Under such a system, all should support such “helping” policy because, given an unfortunate turn of events, anyone in the commonwealth could be at the bottom.
This reciprocal relationship among citizens calls on a meaningful reality that, one, allows an opportunity to improve one’s position significantly, and, two, sets up a cooperative mode of social interaction.  It allows for rational decision-making, maximizing one’s benefits and minimizing one’s costs, but is more encompassing than the marginal analysis of the systems approach (which was described earlier in this blog as an element of the natural rights construct).
Selznick writes that this reciprocal relationship considers the potential and often real disruption that the lack of respect and dignity can cause in the social square or arena and the possibility that anyone or anyone’s loved ones can find themselves in desperate and deprived conditions.  The reciprocal relationship of the arrangement has strong support within its logic for a fraternal ethos upon which community can build and a meaningful commonwealth can be maintained.[4]
But there exists under this logic the temptation to see all inequalities as counter to moral equality.  One needs to be clear on the functions of inequality:
Historically there have been four main justifications for inequalities as contributing to the common good.  It has been claimed that inequalities are essential for: (1) effective organization for prosperity, education, public safety, and similar social goals; (2) achievement of excellence and high standards, especially in the realm of “high culture”; (3) protection of freedom, including the freedom to become unequal in possessions and personal attainments; and (4) commitment to ascriptive unities, especially family membership, which depend on recognition of special benefits and privileges.  None of these objectives can justify unlimited or unrestrained inequality.[5]
To summarize: some level of inequality is both practical and moral; i.e., a moral commonwealth should support an elitist element within its midst.  The elites, who are committed to democratic and republican ideals, are those the commonwealth depends upon to lead the pursuit of a moral society under those ideals.
Included in this ideal is the goal of establishing a community in which the elites and non-elites can live in a cooperative venture.  In short, that cooperative effort is to seek equality that restrains arbitrary power, encourages democratic participation, and promotes effective economic opportunity.
An Equality Aim, A Further ImplicationThis account of federation theory is about what should be taught in civics classrooms, not about constitutional dicta suitable for courtroom argument.  The writer knows his place.  In terms of law, in his humble opinion, the natural rights' manner of defining individual rights is about right; that is, while some things should be changed, even in the direction of federalist thought, by and large a system of laws that supports a more individualistic take on our rights should be sustained.
Legally, one should be able to define basic values and those courses of action one feels are best for his/her individually defined goals.  But such a legal system does not preclude the nation from holding “higher” aspirations for its citizens.  And “higher” is in terms of sustaining the health of the commonwealth.  But, just as those among the citizenry who wish everyone to be religiously moral, few would impose the power of government to enforce such an agenda. 
One can say the same for a law-enforced federalist “theocracy.”  The call is not to jam federalism down anyone’s throat, but for everyone to become aware of its noble history in the development of this nation (including its government and economic system) and its enticing promises to encourage and enable a more communal democracy. 
And that ends this account of how federation theory views government and politics.  What remains is a review of how its adherents would see how its adoption would advance the common good through actual classroom application.  That is the topic that will conclude this presentation of the federation theory construct along with a summary of the blog’s argument to this point.  It will do this by outlining a set of lesson plans that can serve as an example of how federation theory can be implemented.



[1] Philip Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth:  Social Theory and the Promise of Community.

[2] Ibid.

[3] Ibid., 492.

[4] Ibid.

[5] Ibid., 499.

No comments:

Post a Comment