I have made the point in this blog
that at the beginning of our republic, the prevailing mental
construct that, more than any other construct, guided our views
concerning governance and politics was traditional federalism.
Its dominance ended in the post World War II years when the natural
rights construct ascended to dominance. We don't often, these days,
hear in public discourse expressions of thought based on the ideas
and ideals of the older version of federalism. Justice Antonin
Scalia, the other day, expressed an opinion which reflects this more
outdated thinking. Replying to a student's question about why the
justice had equated laws criminalizing sodomy with laws against
bestiality and murder, the justice said, “I don't think it's
necessary, but I think it's effective. … It's a form of argument
that I thought you would have known, which is called the 'reduction
to the absurd' … If we cannot have moral feelings against
homosexuality, can we have it against murder? Can we have it against
other things? … I'm surprised you aren't persuaded.”
To make my point in this posting,
I have to make an assumption. The assumption is that Scalia is
referring to moral beliefs that are based on religious doctrine. I
make this assumption because I am not aware of any other source that
would reject homosexuality on the grounds it is immoral. As such,
and since he was referring to state law, I find this argument, on its
face, to be an expression of traditional federalist thinking.
Our early political development,
as I have pointed out, was heavily influenced by congregational
religious traditions. Starting with the Puritans, people banded
together to form our most basic governmental arrangements mirroring
the process by which they organized their churches. That is, they
came together and through a covenant promised each other a set of
binding provisions which, among other things, set up a government, a
process of governing, a list of goals, and an expression of rights.
The format can first be found in the drawing up of the Mayflower
Compact and has its most encompassing form in the writing of the
United States Constitution. The basic idea is that either
individuals or political entities gather and see that their mutual
benefit is best advanced by them joining in this manner.
A recurring question that results
from organizing in this fashion is how much self rule the parties
retain within the resulting union and how much is handed over to the
political entity that's formed. This basic area of concern has been
with us since the beginning, was central in our political conflicts –
including the concerns that led to us engaging in a civil war – and
is still with us today. Individual, federated partners, no matter
how clear the language of the agreement is or was, when relevant
issues arise, will place their support with the notion that power
lies predominately either with the members of the union or with the
union itself.
There will be those who place
their support for retention of power with the partnering members and
those who will support the union's claim of power. There have been
historical incidences where, given different issues, we have had
individuals who in debating one issue, argued for a strong union and
with another issue, argued that power should be retained by the
members of the union. The example of James Madison comes to mind.
Traditional federalism places the emphasis on the members, especially
when it comes to moral questions. Liberated federalism, the mental
construct this blog has promoted, is not so readily disposed to this
older view.
I have given the name, liberated
federalism, to a view or position that evolves from the earlier form
of federalism. Theoretically, we can find its origins with the
founding fathers. It was already significantly a part of their
theorizing when they went about forming our national government in
1787. But the bit of law that would begin the process that would
undermine the parochial bias of traditional federalism was the
Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution.
Its ratification in 1868 did not
provide a clear delineation between our preference for one view over
the other view. It would take over a hundred years – and the
influence of a completely different construct, the natural rights
view – to undo the theoretical force that traditional federalism
had over our common view of governance and politics. Remember that
in that earlier view, as I indicated above, religion and localism had
strong influence on what was seen as constitutional. This view
assumed that local populations were highly homogeneous. It assumed
that a given locality would have most of its residents attending the
same denominational church, such as Lutheran or Baptist. Under such
social conditions, local communities could express moral positions
without offending people. Diversity was tolerated, but under the
following formula: yes, you have a right to be what you want to be,
but if that way is different, not here; you can be what you want to
be over there. Here, we are this way and if you want to live here,
you have to act accordingly and at least follow what we believe to be
good and proper. But of course, our social development did not
cooperate with this formula. Very early on, diversity became a
disruptive factor. After all, we adopted the national motto, e
pluribus unum.
Even by the time our constitution
was written, a lot of this assumed social character of our
communities was being challenged as we were already becoming more
diverse. Our nation would eventually experience huge immigration
waves of Germans, Irish, Italians, Eastern Europeans, Chinese,
Japanese, Latin Americans, and others. Today, you can go to the most
traditionally leaning communities and you will find storefronts with
Spanish words all over their facades. Take a car trip some day
through small towns in Florida's panhandle and don't be surprised if
you need a Spanish-English dictionary. The whole assumption behind
Scalia's comments is that moral proclivities of local communities, to
the degree his comments would have us believe they exist, simply
don't. At least they don't to the extent that one can justify legal
sanctions on behavior based on religious moral claims. We are too
diverse for this kind of dogmatic view regarding our moral thinking.
Yes, we are still concerned with morality. But, when it comes to
legal restraints, especially when such restraints are aimed at
prohibiting behaviors motivated by natural drives (like the sexual
drive), one needs not religious reasoning but secular reasoning.
Today, natural rights thinking
supplies us with a relatively simple notion that allows for a more
tolerant view of divergent behaviors or beliefs. It simply holds
that if a belief or behavior doesn't – on a reasonable basis –
materially or emotionally hurt someone else, then a person has a
right to believe or act the way he/she wishes. Applying this
standard to the specific topic Scalia commented on – homosexuality
– what someone does in his/her bedroom that doesn't hurt others is
not the concern of others and the law has no legitimate standing to
ban it. But let us say that someone kills someone else in his or her
bedroom. Well then, applying a Kantian notion, what if everyone
behaved that way?1
Then anyone's life is readily in danger. Murder does not have to
have a religious basis for it to be a legitimate subject for legal
prohibition. On the other hand, by any secular standard, someone
engaging in some non-harmful sexual behavior that doesn't pose any
danger to others is, therefore, not subject to sanctions based on
secular grounds.2
The problem is that by adopting a
natural rights view, we lose the communal sense of a locality. We
lose all sense of an “us” and, consequently, everyone is left in
an extremely individually isolated social milieu. We are encouraged
to view our fellow residents as just others and, except for close
friends and family, we lack kinship or emotional ties to others.
But we can't seem to totally
accept such a view. We just experienced watching the Northeast being
battered by a huge storm. We see in the news accounts about how
large sections of communities have been seriously damaged and the
lives of the people profoundly disrupted. The level of physical
damage and resulting heartache affects most of us emotionally. Those
are our fellow citizens and the recent 12/12/12 Concert with the
level of worldwide donations the concert solicited gives testimony to
the fact we, at least many of us, are prone to caring not just for
fellow citizens, but fellow humans. And within those areas during
and immediately following the storm, we hear of selfless, courageous
acts by neighbors who literally saved the lives of others and
otherwise ameliorated the suffering they saw around them. To what
degree they individually hold tolerant attitudes of diverse cultural
mores and customs, of course, is not asked of such people in such
situations. But what we can say is that we find such incidences of
selflessness not only admirable, but reflective of our nature. And
as such, while we might see the natural rights view as sort of
a minimal way to see how we should deal with one another, we tend to
yearn for more personal and interlocking relations.
We often might have natural
defenses against those we don't know and with whom we have no
relationship. But, when we live in communities and there exists a
sense of partnership, we become emotionally involved. Given the
choice, most of us seek such relationships.
These preferences encourage a
federal bias, a bias to allow ourselves to enter federated
arrangements. In modern life this may become more difficult and this
blog has traced some of the social forces that act in opposition to
more communal ties. I believe that one of the reasons for the
difficulties of establishing and maintaining communal ties is our
bifurcated history between the mores associated with our natural
rights perspective and our traditional federalist perspective. I
don't usually do this, but let me share what I found in a study I
conducted.3
I asked a number of high school students in three different types of
communities – rural, semi-urban, and urban – what type of
strategy they would favor if confronted with different problem
situations. One problem was, for example, in deciding vacation
plans, what type of decision-making arrangement would be preferable.
One choice was a federated – shared decision-making –
arrangement. While this doesn't relate directly to the situation
being considered in this posting, it does give us some insight. To
significant levels, the students chose the federated option as
opposed to arrangements that rely on one person deciding, rely on
expertise, or rely on everyone doing his/her own thing. One can
speculate that such a choice reflects the desire for the kind of
interdependence upon which a community is built.
So, we are left with a tension –
the desire for community and the desire to be left to our own
business. Our history, as a nation, has led us to this point: we
seem to have an uneasy accommodation between the two outlooks with
the latter having a virulent default status. I don't believe a
revival of a construct, traditional federalism, that was unable to
meet the demands of a changing social reality, will be helpful. But,
can we totally divorce ourselves from a view that served as the basic
foundation for our constitution? Do we want to stray so far afield
from our original ideas and ideals which were defined by the
congregational model that got us started? The recent communal
examples in the Northeast suggest we don't. On the other hand,
looking around, I can hear some people thinking, please don't impose
your personal lifestyle choices on me or anyone else. We can be
caring neighbors without that; we can be functioning partners with a
reasonable respect for who each of us is.
1You
might ask about the victim in the bedroom. Of course, one might be
concerned with his or her fate, but here I am only commenting on a
minimal basis by which one would consider what can be considered
legal behavior as opposed to illegal behavior. The discussion here
assumes that each member of the social arrangement has no emotional
ties with any other member. Of course, this isn't the way things
are. We do care for others and this aspect of reality is a basis
for criticizing the natural rights construct.
2The
secular case against bestiality, on the other hand, is more
complicated, but there are secular grounds to ban it.
3Gutierrez,
R. (2005). The predisposition of high school students to engage in
collective strategies of problem solving. Theory and Research in
Social Education, 33, (3), pp.
404-428.