One way to gauge how times have changed during
the nation’s history is to compare how people have judged what is right or
wrong, good or bad within different times.
Unfortunately, one cannot interview, for example, early American
colonists. But one can study the
artifacts and written records they left behind.
On that score, one has the work of historians and even political
scientists who have dedicated their professional efforts to look back. As for current views, one need only look at
what contemporary folks have to say or write.
In this effort, one
eminent scholar of the past is the late political scientist, Daniel
Elazar. As for establishing – as this
blog has pointed out – what have been federalist views of morality, Elazar
claims it was the central guide for judging right or wrong, good or bad not
only politically, but in overall social environments. He shares,
Covenantal
foundings [sic] emphasize the deliberate coming together of humans as equals to
establish politics in such a way that all reaffirm their fundamental equality
and retain their basic rights … Polities whose origins are covenantal reflect
the exercise of constitutional choice and broad-based participation in
constitutional design. Polities founded
by covenants are essentially federal in character, in the original meaning of
the term (from foedus, Latin for covenant) …[1]
Those colonists, by agreeing and signing such documents as the Mayflower
Compact, purposely bound themselves to perpetual unions for specified
reasons such as advancing mutual safety, expressing reciprocal respect for one
another, and soliciting or having God as their witness.
A more secular form (actually the more
encompassing category) of this sort of agreement is a compact that consists of
the same type of commitments without a reference to God as a witness. Technically, the Mayflower Compact was
a covenant. Also of note is the relationship
between the terms covenant and federal.
Federalism is derived from basic covenantal agreements. They impose a certain moral view on social
arrangements so initiated – in the case of this quote, the arrangement is a
polity, but one can apply it to other less encompassing relationships such as a
marriage or a business arrangement in which one has meaningful assets at stake.
The point is that such moral bindings
presuppose that people are willing to take on a broadly based moral position. To remind the reader, this sort of concern is
being shared to explain a basic dialectic struggle with which Americans have been
engaged in almost since their origin as a people. That struggle would be federalism vs. natural
rights views of governance and politics as experienced both within and without governmental
interactions.
What of the natural rights view? How does it see things in these realms of interaction
and morality? Again, one can look at
what is being said or written by those who exemplify or act in accordance with
this other view. Probably no source
further demonstrates or expresses the core elements of the natural rights view
than the ideas of a current hedge fund manager who has experienced extraordinary
success.
Fitting that bill is Raymond Thomas Dalio, who is
associated with the Bridgewater investment firm and has amassed a personal
wealth of over one billion dollars. Dalio
has also written a sort of “how-to book.”
And he begins that work by reviewing how one should approach business,
and by implication, life in general.
He writes, “The most important thing I learned
is an approach to life based on principles that helps me find out what’s true
and what to do about it.”[2] He goes on to state that principles are the
foundations of how one should behave to get what one wants. They function to guide courses of action not
only in business but in life in general.
The aim is to satisfy one’s goals.
He encourages readers to give these principles
a good deal of thought. He analogizes
them as recipes that can be applied to similar situations that call on decisions
about how to behave. He addresses the
need for common or shared principles for social arrangements (families,
communities, the nation) but refers only to their functionality and does not recommend
one would adopt common principles per se.
Instead, he emphasizes that one is best served
by having his/her own principles. “If
you can think for yourself while being open-minded in a clear-headed way to
find out what is best for you to do, and if you can summon up the courage to do
it, you will make the most of your life.”[3] So, what is his first principle (and one can
assume, the most important)?
“Think for yourself to decide 1) what you want,
2) what is true, and 3) what you should do to achieve #1 in light of #2 …”[4] Sure, shared principles assuage group
efforts, but that concern is not expounded upon in what he describes. As a matter of fact, Dalio then doubles down
on principles being one’s personal thing by claiming they can be anything one
wants as long as they reflect how one is constituted.
The ultimate “sin” is for one to be phony. And to solidify one’s commitment, one should
write down what one’s principles are – apparently, writing them adds not only
to one’s ability to remember, but to also upgrade the essence of the commitment
to some sort of permanence. If the point
being made here is missed, Dalio reflects natural rights thinking and one cannot
help noting his contextualizing his thoughts in heroic terms.
Now compare that approach to the principled
commitment expressed by the early colonists and founders of the states. Their development was not just an arbitrary
way of doing things but reflected a strongly entrenched cultural
expression. This overarching cultural
value perspective that they expound can be verified by the fact that covenants reoccur
throughout the colonies among groups with little or no communication among
themselves.[5]
From these constitutional commitments, the
resulting governmental development adopted a matrix structure in their arrangements,
i.e., a grid type of structure in which there are many cells that assume high
levels of coordination, cooperation, and collaboration – and, oh yes, common
values. That is, it depends on the
citizenry to be federated in which each cell is a different element of power. This arrangement not only distributes the
levels of control, but also multiplies the access points by which citizens can
seek political satisfaction.
Described in this manner, federalism becomes a
central feature of the nation’s constitutional makeup. It encompasses – and as time has elapsed, in
more sophisticated fashion – the other, often cited principles of the nation’s
constitution: popular sovereignty, separation
of power, and checks and balances. Its
centrality, though, is not one of merely definitional neatness, but one that
maintains the cultural and historical richness of the founding experience.
This posting ends with another Elazar quote:
The
old covenants followed a recurring format or model: … an historical prologue
indicating the parties involved, a preamble stating the general purposes of the
covenant and the principles behind it, a body of conditions and operative
clauses, a stipulation of the agreed-upon sanctions to be applied if the
covenant were violated, and an oath to make the covenant morally binding.[6]
One can easily see that those who entered such agreements, and so bound themselves,
were not making a passive commitment, but a moral one of central importance.
[1]
Daniel J.
Elazar, “Federal Models of (Civil) Authority,” Journal of Church and State, 33, (Spring, 1991), 233-234.
[2]
Ray Dalio, Principles: Life and Work
(New York, NY: Simon and Schuster, 2017),
loc. 60 (Kindle edition).
[3] Ibid., loc 78-88 (Kindle edition).
[4] Ibid., loc 88 (Kindle edition). As a sub note, he adds: “… and do that with humility and open-mindedness
so that you consider the best thinking available to you.” These latter qualities reflect a procedural
concern for what is most utilitarian given human nature, not some concern for
morality.
[5] See for example, Agreement
between the Settlers at New Plymouth (Mayflower Compact), 1620, The
Salem Covenant, 1629, The Watertown Covenant, 1630, Providence
Agreement, 1637, Government of Pocasset, 1638, Fundamental Orders
of Connecticut, 1639, Frame of Government of Pennsylvania, 1682, the
Constitution of South Carolina, 1776, New York, 1777, and Massachusetts,
1780. Each of these colonial and
independent state documents follow the covenantal model of agreement.
[6] Elazar, “Federal Models of (Civil) Authority,” Journal of Church and State, 244.