A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, September 25, 2020

REGARDING JUSTICE AND CIVIL SOCIETY

 

[Note:  From time to time, this blog issues a set of postings that summarize what the blog has been emphasizing in its previous postings.  Of late, the blog has been looking at various obstacles civics educators face in teaching their subject.  It’s time to post a series of such summary accounts.  The advantage of such summaries is to introduce new readers to the blog and to provide a different context by which to review the blog’s various claims and arguments.  This and upcoming summary postings will be preceded by this message.]

 

This blog makes a distinction between how civics’ subject matter is presented in American classrooms and how it should be presented.  How it is presented reflects the guidance that the natural rights perspective promotes.  This blog, on the other hand, promotes the guidance that federation theory provides. 

Naturally, federation theory promotes a federalist view about how reality relating to governance and politics should be conceptualized.  If utilized, lessons would take on a different look from what is common today.  For example, educators might take on the following processes:

·       superimpose a different substantive structure on the subject matter (e.g., place more emphasis on local governance),

·       identify conducive instructional approaches (e.g., have students investigate or be told about local political activities), and

·       place in priority what federalism highlights (e.g., the promotion of civil qualities within local environments such as the school site). 

Overall, federation theory attempts to assist educators in their efforts to promote good citizenship in ways that reflect its ideals.

          But in terms of guiding the work of political scientists, there is apart from the pedagogical view of federation theory another related construct, federal theory.  And to see what distinguishes the two, one might consider the basic aims of political scientists.  To that end, Daniel Elazar identifies three reasons for why political scientists do what they do. 

The purposes or aims of those academics are to pursue the quality of justice, to discover generalizable factors that correlate with various political actions, and to promote a civil society.  Elazar points out that meeting the first two aims helps meet the third.  He relates federalism to “choice” polities by offering it a special character. [1]  That is a character reflecting the qualities of collaboration, community, and mutuality.

          To look at the distinction between the guidance of federal theory and that of the natural rights theory, the former does not look at only the ubiquitous transactional nature of politics.  It extends the interest of researchers to those factors that advance or strengthens normative factors which support a federated partnership that is characterized by the above qualities. 

And this distinction does not look at only what aspects of political reality should be studied, but also the methods used in that study.  Given the almost exclusive transactional lenses political scientists of the natural rights school use, their attention is primarily fixed on the behaviors of political actors.  It is behaviors that have the highest range of observable “choices” upon which political actors act.  Therefore, those researchers mostly “count” on behavioral studies that, it turns out, rely heavily on statistical analysis.

While this more restricted view of political science is prevalent in academia, the fact remains that the American political system is still foundationally based on a compact-al agreement or agreements if one also includes the constitutions of the various states.  And these agreements entail factors that are not always, at least directly or satisfactorily, analyzed through the measurements of behaviors.  For example, this blog’s treatment of the holistic nature of maturation points out that shortcoming.[2]

Research, that sets out to approach the aims Elazar points out, needs to address more than self-defined ambitions.  Substantively, such research needs to look beyond reductionist factors, but seeks methods that address broad, holistic conditions.  And this demands methods that take on broader landscapes than targeted cause and effect relationships.  Yes, those relationships, when proved to be powerful, are important and should be discovered, but more is involved.  Federal theory assists political scientists who wish to pursue grander questions over justice and civility.

One would expect, in a polity where these basic federalist characteristics are well ensconced, that the characteristics or attributes would be part and parcel of the nation’s cultural norms.  As a consequence, the resulting legislated laws of such a system would be ideally well-thought out so as to not jeopardize or undermine the integrity of each partner.  But more is involved. 

A federated arrangement insists that there exists an expectation that citizens take on a proactive posture in the polity’s governance.  This, in other words, would become (and was according to Tocqueville the case in the US of the 1830s) integral to its political culture.  And to the extent it is not, that would indicate how out of favor federalist thinking has become.

On the surface, a federalist mode of behavior and behavior guided by the natural rights view might very well appear the same.  In each, citizens can go about their business basically doing what they want.  But upon a closer look, federated activity seeks to advance the interests of the commonwealth since the citizenry is more apt to seek those ends – at least in the ideal and to a meaningful degree in how those citizens actually act. 

For that to be the case, those citizens need to be disposed to options that consider other than their self-defined interests.  This might very well result in government policies imposing costs on the citizenry, often in the form of higher taxes or other obligations.  And to boot, fulfillment of such support will be more efficient since voluntary compliance would usually be more “normal” and of less cost. 

But as repeatedly noted in this blog, Americans do not primarily ascribe to federation theory.  Instead they predominately hold unto the natural rights perspective.  Consequently, for example, counting on citizens to wear masks during a pandemic becomes problematic.  And that reality affects how Americans define their public morality.  Accordingly, this blog will in the next posting look into the natural rights view of good and bad, right or wrong.   

Why is this a concern?  Since the natural rights view leaves moral questions to the individual – except for its insistence in promoting and protecting the value of natural liberty – that construct maintains a neutrality to almost all other moral precepts.  As such, especially in terms of civics education and its aim to promote good citizenship, how this “sovereign” individual views moral concerns becomes an important aspect of that rubric, good citizenship.

Interested parties might ask of a natural rights guided, civics curriculum:  can one observe where those schools operate, trends in how people make moral choices?  Do the ways people make those choices affect the common welfare?  Do those civics classrooms even address moral questions and, if they do, what strategies do they employ?  Questions such as these will guide what follows in subsequent postings.



[1] Daniel J. Elazar, Exploring Federalism (Tuscaloosa, AL:  The University of Alabama Press, 1987).

[2] See Philip Selznick’s treatment of Hegal’s ideas concerning maturation.  Selznick, Philip, The Moral Commonwealth:  Social Theory and the Promise of Community (Berkeley, CA:  University of California Press, 1992).

Tuesday, September 22, 2020

DEVELOPMENTAL CONCERNS

 

[Note:  From time to time, this blog issues a set of postings that summarize what the blog has been emphasizing in its previous postings.  Of late, the blog has been looking at various obstacles civics educators face in teaching their subject.  It’s time to post a series of such summary accounts.  The advantage of such summaries is to introduce new readers to the blog and to provide a different context by which to review the blog’s various claims and arguments.  This and upcoming summary postings will be preceded by this message.]

Elsewhere, this writer has reviewed a view of America’s past and makes the claim the nation, through most of its history, has held federalism as its dominant view of governance and politics.[1]  But it is the contention of this writer that since World War II, the nation has looked, most predominately, to the natural rights construct for that guidance. 

That occurred after the political culture was subjected to a sort of competition between the two constructs in which federalism through the years lost influence and natural rights gained influence – natural rights finally won dominance in the years after World War II and that dominance has grown in the subsequent years.

          An additional word concerning that competition should be added:  that is, that competition highlighted the vying values between representative democracy – majority rule – and the protection of individual rights.  Through the years, those who were put in charge of making the relevant policy decisions were, to varying degrees, affected by this tension.  They continuously asked:  should policy reflect what the majority, through legislative representation, wishes or should the concern over individual rights be a significant check on what legislative bodies can do?

          Prior to the twentieth century, one can say the bias was toward legislative discretion and even with the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment that bias still held sway.[2]  But once the century turned, starting roughly with the case, Lochner v. New York,[3] 1905, concerning business interests and property rights, the courts began to tilt the scale of justice toward individual rights.  And then came the Warren Court (1953-1969) that blew open the concern for individual rights over majority rule in many areas of jurisprudence.

          Those areas included criminal defendant rights, civil rights (especially those concerning race and gender), cultural expressions, and others.  Of particular note, were issues relating to exclusionary legislation that aimed at depriving individuals and groups from equal access to opportunities and benefits.  And this was, to those favoring the turn, a positive aspect of the natural rights view. 

This writer also welcomes that turn since he judges the many aspects of parochial/traditional federalism, the version that was dominant before World War II, was ironically not as federalist in many important aspects as its basic beliefs would indicate.  That included its definition of who was entitled to be included. 

In the history of the nation, more various European nationalities – not always smoothly – were included in the partnership.  But what seemed to be the limits to such inclusion were the prejudicial beliefs and attitudes toward nonwhite people.  Predominately, the antagonism was aimed at groups of African, Asian, and people of indigenous groups background.  Race was, and still is to a meaningful degree, the bugaboo of American history.

          But can one have a truer version of federalism, one that does not depend on nationalities, race, or other arbitrary limitations?  That would be a federalism that counts on individuals taking on a partnership role that was established by the nation’s and the various states’ constitutions.  This writer believes one can and that version of federalism can be called liberated federalism.  It adopts the basic notion of “foedus” (the Latin term from which “federalism” is derived) or being leagued with fellow citizens through its founding compact, the US Constitution.[4] 

Or stated more commonly, agreeing to being in a sacred partnership.  And under that association, one can consider the natural rights’ judgement that government interference (with its authoritative power) tends to be immoral, seems foreign.  Yes, even a federated government, in structure and process, might be abusive, and it would not be acceptable if it abuses federalist values – one being the dignity of each individual making up the partnership.

But if the legislature does not abuse that and the other federalist values, it has a legitimate role in advancing the common good which along with federal liberty, includes efforts to establishing and maintaining a regulated equality.[5]  A current viable example of this debate or tension is the nation’s efforts to meet the challenge of providing medical care for all citizens. 

And these tensions are played out in schools as well as in any social arrangement dotting the American scene; but it should be formally addressed in the nation’s civics classrooms.  It – majority rule vs. individual rights – should garner an extensive look in civics lesson as those classes shift their concerns to the nation’s political culture.  Those lessons should definitely focus on the relevant contributions that political science provides – how that relevant academic field sees the above issues. 

And that is where this blog will take up this topic in the next posting, but one more word before closing this one.  One should remember that the goals of political scientists do not include making the job of civics teachers any easier.  Their aim is to advance political knowledge, not to teach it to secondary students.



[1] That would be previous postings but instead of listing a set of those postings, the reader can get a sufficient overview from Robert Gutierrez, Toward a Federated Nation:  Implementing National Civics Standards (Tallahassee, FL:  Gravitas/Civics Books, 2020) AND, more formally, Daniel J. Elazar, American Federalism: A View from the States, (New York, NY: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1966) AND Daniel J. Elazar, Exploring Federalism (Tuscaloosa, AL:  The University of Alabama Press, 1987).

[2] Even after the Civil War and the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, the Slaughterhouse decisions upheld local ordinances that protected New Orleans’ establishment of a slaughterhouse monopoly at the expense of competing butchers.  This case illustrates the bias toward representative, law-making bodies over the interests of individual citizens.  One can interpret that bias as one reflecting a more federalist view.

[3] “Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905),” Justia, US Supreme Court, 198, n.d, accessed September 21, 2020, https://supreme.justia.com/cases/federal/us/198/45/ .

[4] Admittedly, this writer is simplifying things a bit.  The initial segregation against “foreign” elements entering the partnership reflected the fact that federal leaguing first gained favor as it grew from religious practices among Protestant, Puritanical, congregational practices.  They formed their church-based communities through the utilization of covenants.  This tradition was established early – through the Mayflower Compact, 1620 – and they, the agreements, would commonly claim allegiance to the British crown and as such, were exclusionary by design.  For a more nuance overview of this process, see Donald S. Lutz, “Introductory Essay,” Colonial Origins of the American Constitution:  A Documentary History, edited by Donald S. Lutz (Indianapolis, IN:  Liberty Fund, 1998), xx-xl.

[5] Regulated as exemplified by laws establishing a minimum wage or minimum health care.