A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, June 9, 2017

THE INITIAL VIEW AND ITS EVOLUTION

It was federalist thinking, as defined in this blog, that gave the nation a strong initial commitment to communal values.  Included in this construct was a view of government and politics that emphasizes a collective bias which holds that citizens are in a partnership.  Here it is called traditional federalism and this construct provided a strong commitment to a set of ideas and ideals historians call civic humanism.
          Civic humanism is central to the collective nature of federalism.  Federalism is not so much a fancy term for states’ rights or an argument that politics should basically revolve around state issues.  While the use of the term here incorporates a lot of this local focus, it is more concerned with the notion that it is about viewing the body politic as just that:  an organic association in which its component entities are highly interrelated and codependent. 
As explained in an earlier posting, a federalist union is formed by the use of a covenant or compact.  A covenant – the word federalism is derived from the Latin word, foedus, for covenant[1]  – or compact is considered a sacred, written agreement among a people or its representatives who want to form an association to accomplish stated purposes.
This process needs to have the parties, as part of the agreement, accept a set of conditions to accomplish those purposes.  As has been stressed in this blog, to further assure that the parties hold true to the agreement, the signatories swear compliance to its provisions.
          It was also stated previously; certain scholars indicate that natural rights ideas and ideals became dominant during the time of the writing of the 1787 national constitution.  This writer disagrees.  Here is why.  While the Constitutional Convention was a definite step away from a purer federalism, its procedures and outcomes were still well ensconced within its penumbra of ideas. 
Here is Forrest McDonald’s account of this argument:
It is a grave mistake, however, to assume from this [the influence of natural rights thinking] that the Framers … cynically abandoned the whole notion of virtue in the republic and opted to substitute crass self-interest in its stead.  Several historians have made that assumption, and at least one has gone so far as to pronounce the judgment that the very tradition of civic humanism, of men finding their highest fulfillment in service to the public, thereby was brought to an end.[2]
While one can logically see the adoption of a bill of rights being an indication that Lockean ideas were becoming dominant, one can also see how it also promotes basic ideals of federalism and republicanism.  Central to the notion of federalism, one of its basic values, is equality.  This sense of equality has an inclusive quality to it; all are equal in this common, organic whole of a society. 
Laws that favor one group over others, as laws often do, pose, at least potentially, a threat to the egalitarian character of a polity.  One can argue that the founders had concerns of any emerging class of business people and that that reflected a more fundamental danger or threat toward the organic nature of a polity.  One should remember, that concern was not limited to the Commonwealthmen, but was the concern that spurred an initial attraction to Lockean ideas. 
The founders were taken with a central analogy:  seeing the health of a polity as akin to the health of an organic being.  Bernard Bailyn reports on the views of John Adams:
So John Adams wrote that a political constitution is like “the constitution of the human body”; “certain contextures of the nerves, fibres, and muscles, or certain qualities of the blood and juices” some of which “may properly be called stamina vitae, or essentials and fundamentals of the constitution; parts without which life itself cannot be preserved a moment.”[3]
This health, it was understood, was negatively affected by abusive laws. 
There are other quotes that could be added, but that is not the intent here.  The intent is to stress that the delegates at the 1787 Convention foresaw a national government functioning within the parameters of federalist values and what historians have come to call “civic humanism.” 
The founders and that generation’s espoused beliefs continued to be supportive of civic humanism, but as a nation its people began to acquire behavioral patterns that further and further, albeit slowly, moved them from this commitment.  More citizens’ behaviors would take on those actions that were aimed at advancing self-interest to the exclusion of those advancing the common good. 
This proceeded to a point which this writer judges to be those years following World War II.  In an informal way, the reader can test this assertion.  He/she could view films shown on Turner Classic Movies and analyze the subtext of feature films and see whether he/she can detect a shift from pre-1945 films and those produced after, say, 1955. 
For example, two films that illustrate this shift, in the opinion of the writer, is the 1930s’ film, Mr. Deeds Goes to Town[4] with Gary Cooper and Jean Arthur and the 1948 film, Billy Wilder’s Foreign Affair (also starring Jean Arthur).[5]  The reader is invited to view those films.  The first film glorifies a communal lifestyle and the second questions those very values as demonstrated by the actions of Americans abroad after the war.
Part of the argument here is that a history, summarized below, of continuous challenges to the dominance of traditional federalism eventually were too much.  Traditional federalism finally was replaced by the natural rights construct.  One might ask:  why did it take so long for this to happen or perhaps did it happen before the post war years?  Of course, this is a matter of degree and fixating the turn to a particular year or to small number of years is guess work. 
The writer believes from various sources, including feature films, that it took until the early fifties to finalize this transformation, but even then, the natural rights view was to be further solidified in subsequent years.  Another factor to this development is that the ascendency was not in a straight line, but through ups and downs. 
Through that history one can point to developments that further encouraged the adoption of natural rights thinking.  In previous postings, the blog outlined the effects of the Puritanical era – a period of fire and brimstone theology, – the softening effect of the transcendental philosophic era, the writing and ratification of the 1787 Constitution, and the writing and ratification of the Bill of Rights.  Subsequent phases that advanced natural rights perspective and helped debase federalist views were:
      The settlement of the West encouraged a rugged individualism that was characterized as being more self-reliant, cruder, more informal, more democratic in an individualistic way, imaginative, and prone to initiating innovations.
      The Civil War recast of the constitutional structure in which state power was seriously restrained, but the states maintained many of their sovereign powers.  This was due to a general reluctance to legislate those prerogatives away or to adjudicate, in the courts, a diminution of those powers.  Further restraint of state power, but a strengthening of federalist based equality, was the writing and ratification of the post-Civil War amendments to the Constitution and Civil Rights acts.
      In the late 1800s, an industrialization shift changed the economy in various ways including the rise of large corporations that took hold at the expense of small businesses that lost the ability to viably compete.  While corporations themselves were organized as collectives, they still counted on a strong sense of individual property rights.  Also, the corporation led to a detachment between ownership and the human intercourse of daily operations through the establishment of stock ownership.  In addition, large corporations led the nation to a national economy – to be followed by a global economy – which undermined local viability to determine public policy at those levels.
      Then, and in response to industrialization, the Progressive Movement and the New Deal followed in which the individual was lost in the maze of large government, but, through the resulting anonymity, found new means of expression which further advanced individualism.  In addition, these measures led the way to a more predominant central government, again at the expense of local government.
      And most recently, the age of technology, especially television, has taken hold.   As a result, a simplistic sense of reality and materialism has replaced the written forms of communication giving the nation truncated language, one lacking in metaphors, and an expectation of being continuously entertained.[6]
With that summary, this review of what constituted traditional federalism is complete.  A summary account of traditional federalism is as follows:  it is a construct based on moral agreements aimed at promoting the common good; it applies this moral view when considering realistic politics whether under the conditions of an arena with its conflicts or of a public square and its alliances to achieve collaboration; and its aim is to enhance two qualities, social capital and civic humanism.
Yet, this blog does not promote traditional federalism.  So, what’s wrong with traditional federalism?  To answer this question, this blog offers a critique and will share it in the next posting. 



[1] Daniel J. Elazar, “Federal Models of (Civil) Authority,” Journal of Church and State, 33, (Spring, 1991):  231-254.

[2] Forrest McDonald, “The Power of Ideas in the Convention,” in Major Problems in American Constitutional History, Volume I:  The Colonial Era through Reconstruction (Lexington, MA:  D. C. Heath and Company, 1992), 160-169, 162-163. 

[3] Bernard Bailyn, “The Birth of Republican Constitutionalism,” in Major Problems in American Constitutional History, Volume I:  The Colonial Era through Reconstruction (Lexington, MA:  D. C. Heath and Company, 1992), 91-97, 91.
. 
[4] Frank Capra (director), Mr. Deeds Goes to Town (a film), (Columbia Pictures 1936).

[5] Billy Wilder (director), Foreign Affair (a film), (Paramount Pictures, 1948).

[6] Neil Postman, Amusing Ourselves to Death:  Public Discourse in the Age of Show Business, (New York:  Penguin Books, 1986).

Tuesday, June 6, 2017

COMMONWEALTH VS. INDIVIDUALISM (pt. 2)

[Note:  This posting is a continuation of the previous entry.  The topic is how the founders of the republic handled the contradicting forces of commonwealth concerns and that of individualism and individual rights.  The previous entry was posted June 2.]

It is helpful to get a good grasp of two questions: how did the founders generally see this debate and what did the overall political culture support?  To begin with, federalist values ultimately counted on free consent, as stated in an earlier posting, not only in terms of joining the federated union, but in meeting the responsibilities upon which such a union relied. 
But one cannot dismiss the level of social pressure that people were under when federalist ideals were dominant in the political culture to fulfill those responsibilities not to mention the proclivity to enact supportive laws.  A noted scholar, Jack Rakove, writes of how government straddled that line between individual prerogatives and commonwealth concerns:
Most important, freedom of conscience becomes the quintessential and paradigmatic liberal right. It goes further than most of the common-law rights simultaneously recognized in the various Revolutionary-era bills of rights. Those rights – even those relating to search and seizure – do not suppose that our activities lie completely beyond the purview of public authority. They suppose only that when the state acts, it must be able to demonstrate its basis for doing so, and then must conform to some set of established norms in carrying out its lawful duties.[1]
In short, the writers and those who voted to ratify the original constitutions of this nation, both at the state and national levels, did not believe in inalienable – meaning unobstructed or undeniable – rights. The phrase in the Declaration, “endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable rights, among them life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness...” really refers to categories of rights; for example, the right of free speech falls under liberty. Liberty itself is inalienable, but free speech is not, as in the often-cited example that you don't have the right to yell fire in a crowded theater.
The only restriction placed on government on limiting a right is that government must base such restraints on a legitimate state interest, such as to “secure domestic tranquility” (stated in the Preamble to the Constitution).
Relating to this concern, the founders held the federated goal to establish a republic.  Structurally, republican government can be defined as a government that is composed of representatives of the people.  But culturally, republicanism demands civically inspired qualities which are characterized by certain attributes.  The argument is that federalist governments allow the polity to meet the demands associated with attaining these attributes. 
What are these demands?  The first is structural in nature.  Government should be small to guarantee a more personal approach to public policy.  This was furthered by the development of covenants and compacts calling on personal commitment and securing a palatable liberty.  One can intuitively see that having the “smaller” state governments addressed this demand (more on this below).
The second demand is that resulting governmental entities, at a given level and given authority, will be treated as equals. But the trade-off is:  each has responsibilities to the union, such as participating in the processes to achieve the union’s purposes. Therefore, they all have rights and duties. As such, given the moral basis of the promissory agreement, fulfilling the prescribed duties and respecting the rights of others takes on a moral character.[2]
The next demand, as stated above, the founders thought in terms of alienable, not inalienable, rights. To add a word on this demand, government, under federalist thought of that day, had a legitimate role in controlling passions such as gluttony, jealousy, salaciousness, and other physiological drives.  An enemy of liberty, it was believed, were those passions that experience has demonstrated to be self-destructive if uncontrolled.  Again, the only caveat is that the state cannot be capricious in its demands of the citizenry. 
In short, a lot of federalist politics in our early history is about the boundary between legitimate and illegitimate exercise of governmental power in what would nowadays be considered the personal aspects of life.  It was believed that since laws were the product of democratic processes, these processes served to protect individual rights – the very people who selected the law-makers, had to live by the laws those law-makers made.
Gordon Wood does point out that this reliance on representative government during the years between the Declaration and the Constitution did become abusive.  In some cases, the “majority” was trampling property rights and culminated in Shay’s Rebellion. (an uprising in which poor farmers wanted to avoid paying taxes).  At that time, therefore, there was a strong, almost radical, preference for collectivism among many Americans.[3]
  This rebellion was one of many events that spurred the calling for the 1787 Constitutional Convention that resulted in our current national constitution. But it is a mistake to see this turn as a complete undoing of communal biases of the Whigs in favor of individual property rights and other individual rights. It encouraged only a scaling back from the more radical stand that some Whigs promoted and this illustrates the diversity of views during those late eighteenth century years.
But responding to a more widespread view, the founders hit on a new model. They saw the problem for maintaining small governing areas an ideal with innate problems. While smallness allowed for more personal politics, they also were subject to dominating factions or moneyed and/or propertied interests tyrannically controlling political affairs – the “company town” syndrome.  Elazar reports that Madison reacted to this.
Elazar writes:  “The interdependence of the national and state governments was to ensure their ability to check one another while still enabling them to cooperate and govern energetically. In the words of Publius, they advocated a republican remedy for republican diseases.”[4]  To avoid a tyranny of a domineering faction or factions, therefore, the same federalist model was applied to a larger configuration and a non-centralized system was created.
It was neither a decentralized nor centralized system, but a non-centralized system. The solution came as close to the demand for personal interaction and respecting smaller entities as possible while incorporating the benefits of a larger political arrangement.  They created the pre-Civil War federalist model which sustained a significant level of sovereign power at the state level while creating a central government with national powers.
With this new format, a central assumption was made regarding the protection of liberty and individualism. That is, there is no central or single power, but several. The result is a system of checks and balances through distributed powers.  With a strong allegiance to communal concerns while furthering the rights of individuals, American republicanism received a strong foundation.  Even in the post-Civil War arrangement, this description held for many years.



[1] Jack Rakove, “Once More into the Breach:  Reflections on Jefferson, Madison, and the Religion Problem,” in Making Good Citizens: Education and Civil Society, eds. Diane Ravitch and Joseph P. Viteritti (New Haven, CT:  Yale University Press, 2001), 233-262, 247.

[2] Daniel J. Elazar, American Federalism: A View from the States, (New York, NY: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1966) AND Daniel J. Elazar, “How Federal Is the Constitution?  Thoroughly,” Readings for classes taught by Professor Elazar (Steamboat Springs, CO:  National Endowment for the Humanities Institute, 1994), 1-30.  A booklet of readings prepared for an institute for teachers. AND Daniel J. Elazar, “Federal Models of (Civil) Authority,” Journal of Church and State 33, (Spring, 1991):  231-254 AND Donald Lutz, The Origins of American Constitutionalism, (Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press, 1988).

[3] Gordon S. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic 1776-1787, (New York, NY: W. W. Norton and Company, 1998).

[4] Daniel J. Elazar, “How Federal Is the Constitution?  Thoroughly,” 21.