A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, March 13, 2020

INPUTS, OUTPUTS, AND FEEDBACK


If the reader has taken up reading this blog with this posting, he/she is helped by knowing that this posting is the next one in a series of postings.  The general concern of this series is reporting on what constitutes contemporary civics courses in US secondary schools.  To this point, the blog has argued that in congruence with the dominant political culture – dominant since the years after World War II – civics curriculum has counted on a view of governance and politics this blog has called the natural rights view.  That bias has affected what is taught in those classrooms.
The reader is encouraged to look up the last five postings[1] if he/she has not read them, but overall, the message has been that civics instruction has reflected a view that emphasizes natural liberty – the right to determine one’s values and the rights to pursue those values – as an ultimate or trump value.  In turn, the presentation of the American political system so guided assumes a citizenry’s concerns with government is more in line with those interests of consumers for governmental services.[2]
In terms of any morals associated with citizenry, current civics treatment follows the advice of the political theorists, Niccolo Machiavelli, governance and politics are amoral – morality has nothing to do with it.  No, instruction doesn’t do this by saying it is amoral but by avoiding moral topics or issues for students to address.  The general tenor of civics instruction is to inform students as consumers as to what government offers and how one can gain access to those services.
The blog has moved on to the point that it is reviewing what political science has to offer.  By way of context, many in that field are also guided by the natural right view.  This is important because civics relies on political science for the bulk of its content.  So, if that academic field of study is following certain theoretical, practical, or methodological biases, that guidance will affect what is taught in secondary schools.
So, how has political science operationalized these amoral ideals?   With a sense of what natural rights advocates hold as their morality/amorality and with a bit of historical foundational information, the reader is now set to see how natural rights advocates view politics and government from an academic perspective. 
What is emphasized here is that many political scientists adhere to the political systems theory and positivist methodologies.  Of course, these elements are described and explained below and in subsequent postings, but what is hoped for is that the reader considers what the implications these choices have on promoting good citizenship – the purpose of civics education – and why an advocate of federation theory would be in disagreement with this approach. 
The natural rights construct has a mostly unified theoretical foundation.  Mainly relying on the work of David Easton[3] from the 1950s and 1960s, educators who adopt the natural rights construct see government as a complex entity whose main function is to provide services.  This entity is characterized as having intra-active components which give it its systemic quality. 
The government or the political system basically takes in demands and supports from the citizenry – inputs – and, responding to those stimuli, issues outputs in the form of policies and other outcomes.  The term “output” is the preferred term for policies – such as laws and regulations.  This writer has heard the quip that calling these laws and regulations output is better than the term, put out (an example of political science humor).
The political systems model views citizens as generally being self-sufficient and mostly capable of solving their own problems.  When confronted with the rare occurrence in which they believe they cannot meet some significant demand on their own, they will seek government action.[4]
Individually, or more commonly through some collective, they communicate to an appropriate government agency(ies) what is desired.  Michael J. Sandel describes this interaction, as pointed out above, as one that takes on a consumer perspective.[5]  Consequently, government is seen as a third-party entity.  This basic view of government holds certain other assumptions to be true. 
They are: one, government's main purpose is to protect the rights of citizens to lead their lives as they themselves determine.  Two, government maintains a neutral position as it oversees a competitive process among citizens as they pursue favorable governmental decisions.  And three, individuals engage in the competitive process from a motivation of self-interest.
Derived from these assumptions, important implications are in play. First, due to limited resources, citizens' demands are usually seeking mutually exclusive outcomes, i.e., one citizen's or one interests group’s gain generally means another citizen’s or interest group’s loss.  Consequently, some citizens will be disappointed, causing issues to arise.  Easton, concerned with this outcome, identified stress management as a main concern for political systems.  Enough unsatisfied and unattended demands can cause stress and if excessive it can lead to the system's collapse or for it to become dysfunctional to a meaningful degree. 
Second, these assumptions make the political systems model highly applicable to the natural rights' emphasis on the individual and its accompanying moral (or amoral) view.  With just a bit of imagination or imagery, one can see how market oriented this view of politics and governance can be.
To emphasize one thing:  if one approaches the typical civics teacher and asks about the political systems model, he or she will probably not know what one is talking about.  Even those who received a degree in political science might not be familiar with the above language.  The political systems model no longer enjoys the dominant position among political scientists that it once held.[6] 
One stills finds the methods associated with systems studies being applied to marketing studies, political campaigning, and other areas of interest.  And it remains the dominant construct in our civics and government classrooms.  This is by default for several reasons.
For one it lends itself to a descriptive approach to government.  Government textbooks view government somewhat as a machine.  It has parts and the parts interact to provide some change that is sought by consumers.  This mechanical view corresponds to inputs (demands and supports in political systems or fuel in a machine), conversion (the government in the political system or an engine in a machine), and outputs (laws, for example, in a political system or the machine's activity, for example moving a car and its passengers). 
Those who promote the political systems model often object to a machine analogy.  They claim that a political system also has feedback, a self-reflected response to the consequences of its output that through certain processes become new demands and supports.  Through this process, a system seeks to attain an equilibrium in which contradictory forces reach a workable balance.  They, therefore, use the analogy of an organism to describe their model. 
For purposes here, though, civics instruction does not address this feedback function very well or at all.  While a prevailing view of governance and politics is motivated by giving students an understanding of this service providing institution, it is mostly made of descriptions and explanations – truth claims about the subject matter – for someone who is being introduced to the apparent elements of a governmental – consumer satisfying – system. 
This approach might sound a bit too simple to account for all political activities.  It needs, one might say, something else.  Well, to provide that something else, Gabriel Almond and G. Bingham Powell, Jr. offer, while not included in the presentations one finds in civics courses, a more rounded view of the systems approach.  Next posting will give the reader an overview of these political scientists’ model, the structural-functional model.
[Note:  This blog in a previous posting, “Back to Basics, I” (February 2, 2020), mistakenly attributed a description of the three options by which polities are initiated (choice, force, and accident) to Federalist Paper, No. 2 by John Jay.  The correct attribution should be to James Madison, Federalist Paper, No. 1.  This correction has been made online.]



[1] The series begins with the posting, “The Natural Rights’ View of Morality” (February 25, 2020).  See Robert Gutierrez, “The Natural Rights’ View of Morality,” Gravitas:  A Voice for Civics,” February 25, 2020, access March 13, 2020, https://gravitascivics.blogspot.com/2020/02/the-natural-rights-view-of-morality.html .

[2] Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1996).
[3] David Easton, The Political System (New York, NY:  Alfred A. Knopf, 1953) AND David Easton, A System Analysis of Political Life (New York, NY:  John Wiley and Sons, Inc., 1965).

[4] Justifying a government role in a capitalist economy, for example, is limited to certain conditions.  Among these conditions is when “public goods” are provided.  That is, public goods are desired goods or services whose consumers cannot be segregated.  For example, a person wants a traffic light at a nearby intersection to make his or her life safer, but since everyone who drives through that intersection would benefit, that person is not motivated to pay for the light.  National security is another example that falls under this category.  Another condition occurs when a market for a product is a natural monopoly – such as electricity.  Generally, monopolistic power has proven to be excessively abusive.  Therefore, the government is deemed justified in regulating such a market.  There are other conditions, but the point is that in order to be legitimate, these government actions cannot be simply initiated by rulers, but need to be justified in a predominately capitalist system as exists in the US.

[5] Michael J. Sandel, Democracy's Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy, (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1996 AND Michael J. Sandel, What Money Can’t Buy:  The Moral Limits of Markets (New York, NY:  Farrar, Straus, and Giroux, 2012).

[6] Initially political systems approach with its related behavioral studies were meant to imitate the natural science approaches with the anticipated successes those sciences experienced starting in the nineteenth century and straight through the twentieth century.  But alas, no such success was being achieved.  Consequently, the political systems approach broke down to various derived approaches like cybernetics, public opinion studies, conflict theory studies, political sociology studies, comparative politics studies, political economy studies, etc.  In addition to this diverse, more specific areas of study, older methodologies are currently held in higher regard. They include philosophic and historical methods.  In addition, more recently, one finds hermeneutics studies enjoying respected standing within the discipline.

Tuesday, March 10, 2020

FOUNDATIONS OF THE NATURAL RIGHTS VIEW

For teachers who teach civics, the discipline of political science formally fulfills the role of being the academic content source, at least for the most part.   When considering the role of a construct in relation to an academic subject, particularly a natural science, there is a broad-based view of the subject matter that prevails among the scholars who do research in that subject.  For example, the theory of evolution plays that role in biology. 
As a social science, though, political science does not have a universally accepted theoretical foundation as exists in biology, physics, or chemistry.  Yet as a study of human endeavors, political science is easily affected by notions of right and wrong – normative considerations – which purely scientific approaches avoid.  From the choices available, civics educators, by and large, have adopted the political systems model as their theoretical foundation and by doing so have turned away from most moral concerns.
They, especially classroom teachers, might not be conscious of that choice; the choice might have been handed to them without their realization.  How?  By mostly assigning them a textbook.  Ask typical teachers why they teach what they teach, and they will probably say something along the lines that what they teach is what their textbooks cover.  In turn, those textbooks in civics follow a natural rights view of government and politics.
As such, this choice of adopting the natural rights view has consequences because any resulting content is logically derived from that construct.  That includes its emphases, questions, and desired outcomes.  Generally, a natural rights construct, by using the political systems model, promotes a view of politics as an overarching procedure that is aimed at arriving at consensus through legitimate, competitive processes. 
This last statement might sound a bit ephemeral.  The upcoming text of this blog, in this and following postings, will outline these elements as it attempts to describe and explain how natural rights adherents view the subject matter. 
On a more basic level, one can ask:  what are the origins of this construct?  There are two theoretical traditions at work. One is the tradition known as the Enlightenment.[1]  The chief idea inherited from the Enlightenment is that humans should operate from a rational basis.  People, according to this view, know what they want, know what their interests are, and should make rational calculations in trying to match their perceived reality with their desires. 
The Enlightenment also gave the scholarly world a deep respect for natural forces and rejects the influence of otherworldly forces.  Therefore, according to these precepts, it is in everyone's interest to learn about the natural environment at least insofar as it affects people.  The means by which one does this learning is best served by using a “scientific method” with a profound reliance on mathematics (in the form of statistics).
The second tradition was initiated by Niccolo Machiavelli.  Machiavelli began what is considered modern political thought.  It stands counter to traditional or classical thought that was founded on the ideas of Plato and Aristotle.  Basically, Machiavelli proposed that people are not motivated, and should not be expected to be motivated, by altruistic goals. 
Therefore, leaders, especially supreme leaders such as princes, kings, presidents, prime ministers, and the like, should rule from a position that advances their power.  Politics is amoral and only power can be counted on to achieve success.  Concern for constituents is limited to those policies that advance the ruler’s (s’) power. 
For example, Machiavelli counsels a ruler not to provide resources to the poor.  To do so would make the ruler seem weak because he or she would apparently be motivated by sentimentality and then hated when he or she could not afford to provide assistance at some inevitable future date.  Machiavelli urged leaders to be both a fox, as in being crafty, and a lion, as in being strong and fearless.[2]
Summarily, these traditions encourage students of politics to see that activity as a no-nonsense aspect of life in which decisions of distribution are made.  The decisions as to who gets what, when, and how are calculated to advance decision-makers, be they in authority or just common citizens, in their interests.  Analysis of and participation in civic activities demand an objective, non-sentimental, and self-serving approach.  One should remember, politics exists in a reality of scarcity in which people ultimately compete “to get theirs.”
The currency of such a competitive landscape is power.  Under this approach, if one holds a political morality that is limited by the relatively simple dictum that everyone should be free to do what he or she wants as long as one does not interfere with the rights of others, then one is left or encouraged to adopt an amoral view of governance and politics.  Those self-centered views lead to an environment in which the individual is left fending for him/herself, family, perhaps friends, and business.
As such, one can readily see how these two traditions can be cited as the foundation for what John Locke developed in the 1600s and how the self-serving aspects of Locke’s work has been influential in the subsequent years, especially in the US.  Part of the consequences of such thinking eventually can be detected in political science when that discipline attempted to imitate the methodologies of the natural sciences during the mid-twentieth century.  More on this to come in upcoming postings.




[1] The Enlightenment was a philosophic development in European history that only affected philosophy but through its tenets affected politics, science, and communications.  Also known as the “Age of Reason,” it took place from 1685 to 1815.

[2] The Machiavellian ideas expressed here are those expressed in The Prince.  Elsewhere, this political writer somewhat softens these “Machiavellian” ideas as in Discourses on Livy.  See Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince (New York, NY:  A Mentor Book, 1952) AND Niccolo Machiavelli, Discourses on Livy (Chicago, IL:  The University of Chicago Press, 1996).  One more bit of advice Machiavelli extends to the prince:  it is good to be both liked and feared, but it is more important to be feared.