A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, April 2, 2021

A CASE OF INTELLECT OR WILL

 

To continue this blog’s view of colonial America, the story to date has established the prevailing religious basis of the New England settlement.  And that religion was based on Calvinist beliefs.  But despite this prominence of Puritans, there developed a serious split within that community.  That was between Congregationalists, who already put distance between themselves and mainline Puritans back in England, and Separatists who further emphasized their rejection of any Roman influence via the Church of England. 

And that separation was hinted at in a few postings ago where the point was made that the reliance on biblical writings and any derived lessons as applied to everyday life should rely on logic.  A problem with that, among some Puritans, was that such reliance, in turn, depended on pagan sources, the classical thinkers such as Aristotle and Cicero. 

To modern ears this might sound as much ado about very little.  But to the purists that engaged in these concerns and who also enjoyed significant influence on leadership of that time, this linkage apparently had effects about how they defined legitimate power.  As such, given the linkage these colonial governments placed on spiritual factors, these debates could and did play a role on what constitutional ideals germinated among these early Americans.

Many of these discussions were held within the walls of Harvard, which was established in 1630 just ten years after the Plymouth colony was formed.  There a certain train of thought seemed to have taken hold.  To begin, those arguments accepted the realistic claim that people attained knowledge or beliefs from what they perceived.  Insight was attained in how one structured the information, the data, one viewed, felt, or heard.  The trick to that intake was to logically order that information.  This order, the belief was, reflected what God imposed on reality.

This “orderly” sense of reality and how people relate to it – as sensible as it might sound to some – was critiqued by a set of religious thinkers.  They expressed their concerns in published works, for example, William Ames’ Medulla Theologica.  Collectively, these thinkers offered an alternative way to view this basic mode of knowing.  Allen Guelzo states,

 

… Ames believed that ethics should not stand as an independent study on its own, with its teachings hammered out by logical connections between moral axioms.  Ames believed that ethics should be studied only as a department of theology, which was a shorthand way of saying that there was no moral truth or theory of moral truths worth studying apart from Calvinistic Protestant Christianity.  “The highest kind of life for a human being,” wrote Ames, “is that which approaches most closely the living and life-giving God.”[1]

 

Ergo, why any reliance on Aristotle or Cicero?  He saw no reason to do so.  The Bible is good enough on its own.

          Ames’ rejection was not so much against logic, but on a logic originating with classical thinkers or natural philosophy of which five branches can be derived:  metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, politics, and esthetics.[2]  Of course of key concern here was with ethics.  How does one establish the good from evil or the right from wrong? 

Within the tradition of Thomas Aquinas, a philosopher and saint within Roman Catholicism, one relies on his/her intellect and that relies heavily on logic.  Ames, utilizing responsible philosophic reasoning, argues that one should rely on will and he used the older ideation of Augustine, who is another saint but of a much earlier time.

          In this tradition, Ames claimed that religious thought should be based more on love (a motivated source of the will) than on objectified logic.  Belief, religiosity, and in turn Christian living ultimately depended on turning one’s will toward God.  In effect, this goes beyond understanding and might even circumvent it. 

On the other hand, the intellect, according to the Aquinas approach, can be called upon to reason out why one should remain loyal to a purified version of the Church of England if the ultimate aim was to reinforce that linkage through a reasoned set of beliefs.

          But if the aim was to strive toward a sincere and complete conscious embrace of the Calvinist beliefs concerning God’s grace and all that that entailed, it depended on a true love.  And one was capable of that commitment if one was chosen to receive God’s grace.  This was designated as Voluntarism and by accepting this view one was giving up on any hope or effort to rehabilitate the Church of England.  On a political plain, this initiated and, once started, fed a growing notion of separation from the mother country.

          Guelzo warns his readers, these concerns were mostly held by the first generation of settlers as they made their way across the Atlantic, settled on the American continent, and began organizing themselves into congregations and political arrangements.  While the above arguments had their place and influence, the day-to-day experiences were taken up by the demands of the wilderness. 

Despite that, Harvard was not giving up on the classical based education.  There reason and logic ruled.  In addition, between 1630 and 1660 a new generation was introduced and socialized into another cultural world than what their parents had experienced.  Besides the natural tendency to entertain these younger members’ own set of beliefs, the intellectual world was moving in other directions and while delayed, due to distance and an ocean, would have its effects on how the younger colonists would see these questions. 

But before moving on, one can detect the origins of independence beginning to take hold.  Probably an initial point or area of contention – one described in this posting – would be spiritual in nature.  And beyond the eastern horizon a new mode of thinking and a new way to appraise authority was brewing.  Would the winds of change challenge the basic federal model the settlers had established on the shores of North America?



[1] Allen C. Guelzo, The American Mind, Part I – transcript books – (Chantilly, VA:  The Teaching Company/The Great Courses, 2005), 29.  The factual information of this posting is derived from this source.

[2] For quick reference, see “Introduction to the Five Branches of Philosophy,” Objectivism 101:  Tools for Living (n.d.), accessed April 1, 2021.

Tuesday, March 30, 2021

OTHER RELATED “CONSTITUTIONAL” TERMS

 

By analyzing language one can garner a good deal of what the motivations of people are.  And that goes for the foundational documents early settlers used to organize themselves politically.  Reviewing those documents not only informs one of the structural and procedural elements of those early governments, they also contained the underlying values and beliefs of those settlers and, in their way, give one the initial political biases they brought to the task of their self-governance.

          In turn, they betray what these people anticipated their politics would be like or what possibilities they could, as polities, pursue.  This was no small matter if one considers the social and physical challenges these people faced.  They were embarking on establishing a society in a raw natural environment.  How they fashioned their collective decisions would play no small role in how successful they would be.

          Donald S. Lutz[1] presents and reviews many of these early documents and prefaces the effort with a review of the terms that repeatedly appear in those documents.  The last posting shared and described a set of those terms.  That posting emphasized the variance those documents expressed between the specific provisions contracts contain and the more emotive, descriptive, and value laden content of compacts and covenants. 

That posting ends with the hopeful role that “organic acts” can provide.  They are an “after-the-fact” sort of addition to a compact and a way to tailor general compact-al concerns and resulting language to the demands of everyday life and the need to establish reliable law.  Lutz introduces this concept by writing,

 

An “organic act” is one that codifies and celebrates an agreement [such as an initial compact] or set of agreements made through the years by a community.  In this way, a “common law” comprising legislative and judicial decisions made over a number of years can be codified, simplified, and celebrated in dramatic form, thereby also renewing the consent-based oath upon which obligation to the community rests.  The early state constitutions adopted in 1776 could be viewed as organic acts as well as compacts as they usually summarized and codified what the colonists of each state had [by the time of independence] evolved over the previous 150 years.[2]

 

What this writer takes from this description is that in a democratic-republican modeled arrangement there is always room for change and the actors never feel they are beyond being questioned or amended in their efforts.  Even the best of plans can be improved upon or abandoned if reality indicates they should be.  Yes, when it comes to “constitutional” issues, the change should have more hurdles to overcome, but its possibility is never beyond consideration. 

And in terms of contracts and their shortcomings, organic acts do not have reciprocal provisions – they are not transactional instruments – since they reflect communal commitments in the governance of a people.  They, therefore, can be considered extensions or “improvements” of original efforts.

This above description introduced another term.  That is “agreement.”  Here, the use of this term falls mostly as one understands the term – an arrangement between or among parties.  Covenants and compacts are agreements.  But of importance to the federalist mind is that agreements imply or spell out a sense of coordination, collaboration, and cooperation.  And, of importance, is the connoted or implied element of free-willed consensus or, at least, acceptance.

This last bit of language should be remembered when a prominent religious or otherwise moral authority attempts to impose moral views on a population that does not totally share in its views or beliefs.  Here, the track record of Americans is not so consistent with this requisite.  There have been extended periods in their history when not only religiously based prohibitions have been imposed, but also its legitimacy has not even been questioned.

Religion or other moral systems can inform a federated body, but it cannot legalistically impose its dictums on a federated arrangement like that of the US without providing a secular justification for such imposition.  One readily thinks of attempts to do so when one considers any plans to overturn the Roe v. Wade decision in its overturning of state laws banning abortions. 

And another quality of such accords is that they encompass more than what a contract entails in terms of its generality.  To remind the reader, contracts are specific in their elements or attributes, they denote reciprocal expectations between or among the parties, and they usually have a specified time frame.  Agreements can have such specification, but not as a definitional requisite.

Another highlighted term is “charter.”  This term, to this writer, offers a bit of confusion.  While the thrust of these documents reflect volition on the part of settlers and resulting “citizenry,” charters are issued by high authority – usually a monarch or some business entity which in the mercantile age were, in turn, chartered by the Crown.  Probably the most famous charter was the Magna Carta. 

Generally, charters were issued to grant permission to commit some act(s) if the actor(s) meet certain provisions – earlier in this review of these documents and history, the Puritans acquired a charter to establish the Plymouth settlement claiming it to be a proposed commercial enterprise.  This was by all accounts stretching the truth, but it worked not only for the Pilgrims of 1620, but for subsequent Puritan groups that made the trip over the Atlantic.

To give the reader a range of purposes for these charters, Lutz offers the following listing of goals for which they were issued:  grant pardon, incorporate boroughs, universities, companies, and other corporations.  They could also convey property from one entity to another.  In general, charters took on a more contractual form by highlighting fairly specific anticipated results from their issuances.

The last term this review will describe is “constitution.”  Derived from the term, “constituent,” the concern here relates to what elements or characteristics need to be present to make something what it is.  For example, a constituent element of a novel is words.  They, therefore, communicate the act or acts establishing, making, decreeing, or ordaining something by those legitimately considered in authority to do so.

So, constitutions have two attributes considered essential in their meaning – they are legitimately issued by appropriate authority and they denote the resulting structure with implied or denoted related processes of some created entity.  Technically, the US Constitution contains more than its “constitutional” elements.  For example, the Preamble is not part of its constitution (with small case “c”), but the document describing the Presidency is.

For the purposes here, that will suffice in terms of the terms this writer feels are important for the reader to consider when reflecting on the compact-al qualities the US Constitution has.  Other terms that Lutz reviews include “combination,” “frame,” “fundamentals,” “ordinance,” and “patent.”  The interested reader can acquire a copy of Lutz’s edited book for the respective definitional notes he shares.

This blog with the next posting will pick up with the ongoing story line of how the US Constitution came about.  What one needs to keep in mind, the emphasis of this review is focused on espoused values of these early Americans with references to events as they relate to those values. 

It will become necessary to look beyond those values to actual behaviors, but the reader should keep in mind that this writer does not believe such values equate to actual behavior patterns.  So, for example, while one can ascribe lofty beliefs about freedom and equality and justice to the founding generation, one can read of very self-centered behaviors being exhibited by those very people.[3]



[1] Donald S. Lutz, “Introductory Essay,” Colonial Origins of the American Constitution:  A Documentary History, edited by Donald S. Lutz (Indianapolis, IN:  Liberty Fund, 1998).

[2] Ibid., xxxi.

[3] For example, see Ray Raphael, A People’s History of the American Revolution:  How Common People Shaped the Fight for Independence (New York, NY:  Perennial, 2002).