A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, January 5, 2024

LIBERALISM’S LACK OF EXPLICITEDNESS?

 

Adam Gopnik offers an insightful description and explanation of the origins of liberalism – tracing that origin to the 1860s and the contributions of John Stuart Mill and Harriet Taylor[1] (see previous posting, “Romantic Liberalism” [2]).  Through his review, Gopnik establishes that essential to liberal thought and speech (their critical words), they go beyond “liberty” and “democracy” and include “humanity,” “reform,” “self-realization,” “pluralism,” and “autonomy.” 

These terms reflect the establishment or the strengthening of a self-selected community with its governance – the creation of which is not accidental but due to reflected action.  That describes a federated arrangement in which a people come together and establish, by common consent, the polity that will govern them. 

And in addition, that polity will govern with a sense of shared purpose, that being “eliminating cruelty and sadism and needless suffering from the world.”[3]  But how specific are these ideas that one associates with liberalism or how well are they combined to show one the way to a better society? 

Here, Gopnik takes a bit of a turn in his explanation and feels it necessary to describe the role that town centers played through the centuries in how liberalized life became possible.  More than merely being symbols for this view or belief of common folk having a say in governance, town centers or the Italian piazza played a central role through the centuries.  It is not by accident that these centers became targets of such authoritarian powers all the way back to the times of the ancient Persians and Spartans. 

These centers often served as markets as they provided the practical reason for townspeople to gather, but they functioned beyond providing provisions.  They became centers for sharing concerns and voicing demands and wishes.  They also provided face-to-face contacts among the townspeople where empathy could develop and strengthen.  In terms of Western democratic tradition, the Greek agora played that important role.

More currently, a good deal of liberalism, as a thought-out construct, can be traced to the Enlightenment of the seventeenth century, but its definitive character, according to Gopnik, seems to have been established in the 1859-1872 period and he gives a good deal of credit to Mill’s contribution, On Liberty (along with Charles Darwin’s Origin of the Species).  Historically, along with these written sources, there were also the historical events of the American Civil War and the establishment in France of the Third Republic.

Gopnik explains:  “Darwin’s was a new articulation of the history of life and humanity’s place within it, implicit but obvious, and Mill’s was the articulation of a new understanding about the nature of authority and the individual’s claims against it.”[4]  And given the events of the mid to late 1800s, people were more apt to reconsider the culturally determined place that average people should take in the political landscape. 

The North winning the American Civil War with its emancipation of slaves prodded democratization beyond American borders.  It encouraged it in Britain, for example.  It reenergized democratic forces in France.  And it threatened authoritarian voices in Germany under the leadership of Otto Von Bismarck while enhancing the socialist message of Karl Marx.

This indicates a bit of diversion and, as such, reveals a lack of a pointed message.  That would be a message with a definite plan for a perceived future that would put into effect the favored democratic governance.  Instead, what emerged was an idealistic vision based on broad democratic principles.  In turn, this allowed these varied reactions just mentioned and reflected its lack of rulemaking or definitive direction. 

Gopnik writes:  “It tends to hold implicit and explicit ideas about community, reform, violence, sexual roles, and more.  Liberalism … is an attempt to realize liberty, not merely to invoke it or make it the subject of an incantation.”[5]  In the opinion of this blogger, this reflects a looseness in definition or theoretical rigor.  And this lack of definitiveness plagues liberal advocates to this day. 

It allows for such offshoots as those mentioned above or for the natural rights view that disdains any social or legal restraints on human behavior on just about any level of social concern – from laws to norms to habits.  As this blog has repeatedly claimed, this last view took dominance in the US in the years following World War II and has grown in its influence ever since.

With that transition, the general sense of duty and obligation of citizenship – which was described in the last posting and is part and parcel of Mill and Taylor’s promotion of liberalism – has eroded.  In its stead, a contractual – quid pro quo – view has taken hold and dismissed a compact-al – partnership – view that had been dominant in the US from America’s colonial period to the mid-twentieth century.

And this blogger believes that that transition has been highly instrumental in generating the increasingly polarized politics that the nation is currently experiencing.  Surely the argument of this posting could be more solid in its reasoning, but it is offered as an interpretation.  That is, liberalism as experienced today has become radicalized.

Whether liberalism, in its essence, has gone through various forms from its inception, readers have a good dose of latitude to judge.  As for this blogger, he would like to see a re-establishment of Mill and Taylor’s apparent bias toward federated ideals and away from radical liberalism.



[1] Adam Gopnik, A Thousand Small Sanities:  The Moral Adventures of Liberalism (New York, NY:  Basic, 2019).  The factual claims of this posting are based on the information this source provides.

[2] Robert Gutierrez, “Romantic Liberalism,” a posting, Gravitas:  A Voice for Civics, a blog, accessed January 3, 2024, URL:  https://gravitascivics.blogspot.com/2023_01_24_archive.html.

[3] Gopnik, A Thousand Small Sanities, 14.

[4] Ibid., 14.

[5] Ibid., 17.  Emphasis added.

Tuesday, January 2, 2024

ROMANTIC LIBERALISM

 

This blog introduced to its readers the work of Adam Gopnik back in January 2020.[1]  His book, A Thousand Small Sanities,[2] gives, early in its text, a history lesson of how “liberalism,” as a political form of thinking, got started.  He traces the roles that John Stuart Mill and his intimate partner, Harriet Taylor, played.  Skipping their adulterous relationship, their interchange in terms of basic political discourse led to a more formal construct about what political speech and behavior should be and became known as liberalism.

          More specifically, along with a strong stand against slavery back in the 1860s, they also advanced ideals such as claiming the equality between the sexes, i.e., that women were entitled to equal standing in society – including the right to vote.  While racial emancipation was a more accepted ideal at that time, this couple were among the initial advocates for women’s rights and for extending to them the franchise.  And before one ascribes to them the title of extremists or radicals of their time or of some ideology, Gopnik claims they were centrists.

          Gopnik shares the following:

 

What they were was realists – radicals of the real, determined to live in the world even as they altered it.  Not reluctant realists, but romantic realists.  They were shocked and delighted at how quickly women and men began to meet and organize on the theme of women’s emancipation, but they accepted that progress would be slow and uncertain and sometimes backward facing.  They did more than accept this necessity.  They rejoiced in it because they understood that without a process of public argument and debate, of social action moved from below, the ground of women’s emancipation would never be fully owned by women nor accepted, even grudgingly, by men.[3]

 

And how does this concern relate to federation theory, the topic of this blog?  It helps explain how the national – in this case, the British – partnership truly expanded as this newer stream of argument, liberalism, took hold among change agents of those years.

            Perhaps, as Gopnik suggests, their personal romance played a functional role in their thinking over the issue of emancipation and extending the franchise.  They introduced, on a more conscious level, the romantic element of how fellow citizens should, according to their view, engender a more useful mode of thinking and feeling. 

And what one might at first blush consider contradictory, if one’s views of others is based on some level of love, how one views them “jives” with liberty.  That is, it simultaneously beckons people to be themselves but also to be concerned with and to take care of how one is seen by others.  Moreover, this leads to a very essential dispositive stance in a federated arrangement of a partnership; that is, to be disposed to compromise. 

“Compromise is not a sign of the collapse of one’s moral conscience.  It is a sign of its strength, for there is nothing more necessary to a moral conscience than a recognition that other people have one, too.”[4]  It’s a sense which ties legitimate disagreements beyond the competing interests under debate.  And in that, one can envision a sense of liberty removed from the natural rights – “I can do what I want as long as I don’t deprive others of the same right” – view. 

For as with this more federated view, one is removed from this unattached individualism that the natural rights view promotes.  How?  It is tied to a view of liberty that acknowledges the obligations and duties true love demands.  Yes, this sense of limitation is not mandated by law, but by emotional ties, that loving relationships entail.

Gopnik leaves his readers with an analogy that this blogger wants to share, for it is a bit unexpected.  That is:

 

Most political visions are unicorns, perfect imaginary creatures we chase and will never find.  Liberalism is a rhinoceros.  It’s hard to love.  It’s funny to look at.  It isn’t pretty but it’s a completely successful animal.  A rhino can overturn an SUV and – go to YouTube – run it right over, horn out.[5]

 

And with that comparison, this posting sets up the next one; it will look at some of the implications from Mill and Taylor’s thoughts.



[1] Robert Gutierrez, “Turn Left,” a posting, Gravitas:  A Voice for Civics, a blog, accessed December 30, 2023, URL:  https://gravitascivics.blogspot.com/2020_01_19_archive.html.

[2] Adam Gopnik, A Thousand Small Sanities:  The Moral Adventures of Liberalism (New York, NY:  Basic, 2019).

[3] Ibid., 11.

[4] Ibid., 12.

[5] Ibid., 13.