A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, September 9, 2022

JUDGING THE NATURAL RIGHTS VIEW, XII

 

An advocate of natural rights continues his/her presentation[1] …

In summarizing the political systems model, this blog left readers in the last posting with the notion that that model avoids prescriptive language.  In addition, it does not purport to recreate all the components of government.  Instead, it is a model, an abstraction of the entire governmental entity.  But in terms of the needs of a citizenry – the governments’ consumers – the model is delineating enough to cover the “waterfront” while ignoring any prescriptive concerns.

          That is, in utilizing this model, students of governance and politics are not exposed to any messaging that promotes the type of citizen they should be.  Its use directs its explanatory efforts without guiding them to what constitutes idealized citizens.  It respects the users’ rights to determine their own roles a priori as to what any aims or goals they might aspire.

          Therefore, the power of the construct is not teleological in any sense other that defending personal rights.  Instead, its strength lies in providing a practical approach which is available for the use of the potential political participants, if participation is the option they choose.  Under that perspective, the systems construct provides powerful insights as to the parameters and processes accessible and functional to participants.

          In terms of precision, Eugene Meehan’s next question of viability, vis-a-vis social science models,[2] the construct does not guarantee to potential users that it will be as precise as they need it to be.  Application of the construct needs to be experienced by active participants.  And with practice, it will most likely perfect – i.e., extend its functionality – in its use.  This, though, is beyond the scope of secondary education, though discussion of its use by secondary students can address this practical concern.

          Perhaps case studies can be read and analyzed in classroom work, but the lack of maturity, reference, responsibility, and genuine interests on the part of students would most likely limit the usefulness of such attempts.[3]  As an adult, actively engaging in political conflicts, familiarity with systems descriptions will probably give people, including those secondary students, an advantage that others without such knowledge would not have.  That is, the objective and inherent “clinical” perspective can and does offer citizens a no-nonsense view of governance and politics.

          Does this construct have the same control over the set of situations it is explaining?  In the sense of generic explanations, it does.  This is, as stated in the previous posting, an approach which allows students of politics to formulate a more specific theory for a government, an agency, or the political situation with which that citizen has a concern.  In that sense, the construct has reliability.  Also, the components of the model are used in a similar manner no matter the level of government or agency under consideration.

          This construct does provide a one-to-one correspondence with those factors which consumer-citizens can avail themselves of in that it gives users a more in-depth appreciation of the complexities involved in political frays.  For example, when citizens forward demands, they might be assisted by an appreciation of how those demands affect various functions. 

That is, the applications of the construct to particular governmental entities or sub-entities that deal with specific issues, will elicit the viable structures, processes, and functions in related political situations.  As such, they encourage citizens to look beyond the immediate factors or conditions that their desires or activities might affect or by which they might be affected, to broader political landscapes.

          For classroom use, once the more prevalent structures, processes, and functions of overall political systems are identified by curricular developers, instructors of secondary students should present and explain them in their classroom presentations.  They can further contextualize these components by highlighting how they operate in actual political challenges. 

Through the instructional strategies of the essentialist school of thought, the students in turn should learn them as working components to their knowledge base.  In this way, their knowledge will enjoy an isomorphic reflection of the most viable factors – structures and processes – in the political arena.

          Not only does the political systems construct have the structural-functional model as a spin-off, but there have been, as listed in the last posting (and will not be repeated here), several other theoretical models that owe their origins to this more general model.  Compatibility with other models is strongly established by the historical role that political systems played in the 1950s and 1960s in encouraging the establishment of these different models of analysis in political science.

          It still holds a central position among those political scientists who argue for the discipline to be, but for a qualifier, a more scientific/positivist field of study; that qualifier being that systemic studies should concern themselves with social issues that have broad, current concerns in a society.  This spirit is captured in the following,

 

Discussions on political economy [a sub area of concern] sought to adapt “grand theories” to specific local circumstances and linked economic transformation to mental, social, and political change, thus making “backwardness” more than just a sum total of economic facts.[4]

 

Or stated in line with the concern here, be it political economy or any other political topic, systems is currently normative enough to address those issues over which citizens invest emotional energy.

          Also, of concern in regard to classroom use, is whether this construct is compatible with varying ideologies of the political spectrum.  Does it accommodate or allow citizens/students from the broad array of political biases to benefit from its use?  To answer that question, one is encouraged to find sufficient commonality among those with varying ideological positions.  According to Michael Sandel, Immanuel Kant’s philosophic reasoning offers such a common stand. 

If the arguments derived from Kant’s philosophical position augments justice, and sanctifies, as a primary value, individual rights – the focus of political systems research – one has a common point upon which to base a theoretical foundation.

          Sandel writes,

From a practical political point of view, the positions of Rawls and Nozick are clearly opposed.  Rawls, the welfare-state liberal, and Nozick, the libertarian conservative, define between them the clearest alternatives the American political agenda has to offer, at least where issues of distributive justice are concerned.  And yet, from a philosophical point of view, they have much in common.  Both offer instead [of utilitarianism] a rights-based ethic said to secure the liberty of individuals more completely.  Although Nozick’s account of rights owes much to [John] Locke, both appeal to Kant’s precept to treat every person as an end and not merely as a means, and seek principles of justice that embody it.  Both deny that there exists any social entity above or beyond the individuals who comprise it.[5]

 

Therefore, the political systems model that emphasizes the behavior of individuals in its analysis is highly compatible with the current range of popular ideological positions.  It can also be judged as neutral in the ongoing political battles the adherents of those ideologies conduct with their opponents.

          And here is a good place to break.  The next posting will introduce the methodologies this construct favors or upon which it relies in guiding political studies – not necessarily guiding classroom instructional strategies.  As for Meehan’s concerns, an advocate of behavioral/positivist studies – those based on political systems model or one of its “off-springs” – argues that this construct holds up well.



[1] This presentation continues with this posting.  The reader is informed that the claims made in this posting do not necessarily reflect the beliefs or knowledge of this blogger.  Instead, the posting is a representation of what an advocate of the natural rights view might present.  This is done to present a dialectic position of that construct.  This series of postings begins with “Judging Natural Rights View, I,” August 2, 2022.

[2] Eugene Meehan in the mid-twentieth century.  He provides the following list of criteria by which one can evaluate or ask questions of any theory, but given its thrust, they seem most applicable to scientifically derived theories. The list is:  Comprehension, Power, Precision, Consistency or Reliability, Isomorphism, Compatibility, Predictability, Control.  See Eugene J. Meehan, Contemporary Political Thought:  A Critical Study (Homewood, IL:  Dorsey Press, 1967).

[3] This area of concern is not limited to the US.  See Gema M. Garcia-Albacete, “Promoting Political Interest in School:  The Role of Civic Education, Research Gate (October 2013), accessed September 7, 2022, https://www.researchgate.net/publication/257924763_Promoting_political_interest_in_school_The_role_of_civic_education. 

As for the US, this concern has been an item of concern for many years.  For example, see John J. Patrick and John D. Hoge, “Teaching Government, Civics, and Law,” in Handbook of Research on Social Studies Teaching and Learning, edited by John P. Shaver (New York, NY:  New York, NY:  MacMillan Publishing Company, 1991), 427-436.

[4] Balazs Trencsenyi, Maciej Janowski, Monika Baar, Maria Falina, Michal Kopecek, “The Political Implications of Positivism,” in Modern Political Thought in East Europe:  Volume I:  Negotiating Modernity in the “Long Nineteenth Century (February 2016), accessed September 7, 2022, https://academic.oup.com/book/7012/chapter-abstract/151355070?redirectedFrom=fulltext.  Again, a more historical perspective – that is from some years ago – see John G. Gunnell, “Political Theory and Political Science,” in The Blackwell Encyclopaedia of Political Thought, edited by David Miller, Janet Coleman, William Connolly, and Alan Ryan (Cambridge, MA:  Blackwell Publishers, 1987), 386-390.

[5] Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (New York, NY:  Cambridge University Press, 1992), 66-67.

No comments:

Post a Comment