A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, June 3, 2016

YOU KANT KNOW A MIRACLE

In my last posting, I brought up the effect that post modernism has had on critical theorists; that is, the strain of thought that has promoted the idea that we cannot be about the business of stating anything definitively about the world around us.  In their eyes, there seems to be a disconnect between what we see and what we know.  From where did this sort of thinking come?  Well, there is a line of thinkers stretching all the way back to the 1700s that laid the groundwork for this view.  It probably starts with David Hume, but this posting is going to share the thoughts of Immanuel Kant and his epistemology.

To establish the context a bit, there was an ongoing philosophical debate between philosophers who saw the way to seek truth was through the use of reason and those who counted on our ability to understand reality through perceptions.  Those who counted on reason saw our main tool in figuring out the nature of reality was our minds and the internal mechanizations we perform in our efforts to understand what is, be it the physical world or the supernatural world.  The second group, the empiricists, relied on their senses, what they saw, smelled, and/or tactilely felt.  This debate, in one form or another, has a long lineage.  One can consider the differences between Plato and Aristotle to be one version.  Anyway, it is into this backdrop that Kant contributed his thoughts.

With a nod to Hume, Kant accepted the former thinker’s claim that we cannot experience cause and effect relations.  From there, Kant’s argument begins by accepting and rejecting portions of both the reason based argument and the empiricists based argument.  He felt that in both these camps, there were understatement and overstatement.

Let us start with the empiricist side.  Kant claimed that we rely on our senses to “see” the world; it is through our senses that we acquire the material of our knowledge.  But immediately, our mind comes into play in that it provides the form in which the perceptions are received.  It is like water in a pitcher; the water conforms to the shape of the container.  So does the information our senses pick up; the mind shapes that information.  Some might use other analogies, such as the mind provides the “glasses” by which we view reality.  What is understood or registered in the mind is shaped by the mind in certain ways.  These ways do not, according to Kant, exist in reality, but are how we adopt the information.

So what does the mind add to this process?  Well, the mind is programmed to see the world through certain lenses (the glasses metaphor).  For one, we see things in terms of a certain context of space and time.  This framework he called “forms of intuition.”  We, according to Kant, cannot escape this disposition.  The framework imprints what is perceived and, if you will, translates the information into this language of time and space.  Kant likened this insight to the disruption Copernicus caused when he pointed out that the sun does not revolve around the earth, but that the earth revolves around the sun.  That bit of discovery had an enormous effect on how we saw reality.  Likewise, Kant felt understanding the mind’s function in defining how we saw reality equal to a Copernican Revolution. 

But the effect of the mind does not end there.  There is another inescapable disposition.  We see something happen and we automatically ask why it happened; in other words, we are disposed to look for cause and effect.  This claim is more in line with Hume’s contribution.  The important lesson is that there is a distinction between things as they are and things as they are to the person perceiving them.  Empiricists – that is scientists – today readily succumb to this claim.  They, in their research, do not contend that they discover cause and effect relations; they merely report correlation.  That is, they issue “X happens, Y happens” sort of statements – it is their theorizing that makes cause and effect contentions and even there, they are hypothesized.  They are never proffered as facts or truth and, ala Karl Popper, their job is to disprove assertions, not to prove them.

Are there any readily observable phenomena that indicate this disconnect to be true?  The cat example has been offered.[1]  Say there is a cat lying on the floor of a room and a ball rolls in her general direction.  What does the cat do?  Chances are, she will jump at it and begin to paw it around.  Now say an adult is sitting in that room and a ball rolls out; he or she is bound to question why this ball is rolling out here; who rolled it?  The mind of the cat shaped the information one way; the adult’s mind shaped it another way – same view, different mental operation.  A young child, on the other hand, will probably not do either.  He or she might just look at it, not knowing what to do.  Why?  Because the history of the child’s perceptions has not experienced this occurrence or anything like it before and hence, the information is novel.  There are no references to define what is happening.  His/her mind does not contain the material and, therefore, the information cannot be shaped.

An average person’s reason does not allow this lack of material to stymie its reasoning.  And with that, we enter another realm of this concern.  It seems that when confronted with novel or unperceivable aspects of our existence, assuming we have mostly worked out answers to most of our daily events, we still look for cause and effect.  Our reason might ask: where does reality come from; is it infinite; what is the fate of humankind?  Such questions ask about things we cannot perceive, but our reason – our mind – seeks cause and effect answers to such questions anyway.  The one question that drew a lot of concern from Kant was, is there a god?  Confronting this question, one is immediately aware that that question relates to a bit of potential reality we have not and cannot perceive.  Therefore, without being able to perceive the subject matter, we cannot “know” an answer.  We can believe in the existence of God only by faith.  And from all indications, Kant had a good dose of that.

I believe that what spurred a great deal of this line of questioning among philosophers during the years after the Enlightenment had to do with the Protestant Reformation.  Before this time, there was a good deal of uniform belief as to what constituted the real and a lot of that belief was defined by Catholic theology.  But once that was undercut, not by just one set of opposing religious views, but by a slew of them, the threshold was past.  Truth no longer was the inspired message from above, but to be “constructed” through our individual effort, via a good conscience, to determine the answers to the questions posed by our existence.  In that pursuit, we have our own, individual attempts to make sense of it all.  To do that, we had to work with the tools we had/have and, according to Kant, that was/is our ability to perceive and to reason.  Each has its role.  But these roles take place at the individual’s level and are apt to not only be inconsistent to the results of others, but also to be inconsistent for the individual over time.  People change their minds about what they believe to be true all the time. 

This quest to figure out how we formulate what we “know” or believe is still an active area of concern.  Recently, among psychologists and other social scientists, they have gained, for example, a newfound respect for emotions and their role in our reasoning processes.  It is this type of questioning we still are actively asking and investigating.  For practical and intellectual reasons, many find this questioning fascinating.



[1] Gaarder, J.  (1996).  Sophie’s world:  A novel about the history of philosophy.  New York, NY:  Berkley Books.  This is a delightful review of western philosophers. 

No comments:

Post a Comment