A Crucial Element of Democracy

This is a blog by Robert Gutierrez ...
While often taken for granted, civics education plays a crucial role in a democracy like ours. This Blog is dedicated to enticing its readers into taking an active role in the formulation of the civics curriculum found in their local schools. In order to do this, the Blog is offering a newer way to look at civics education, a newer construct - liberated federalism or federation theory. Daniel Elazar defines federalism as "the mode of political organization that unites separate polities within an overarching political system by distributing power among general and constituent governments in a manner designed to protect the existence and authority of both." It depends on its citizens acting in certain ways which Elazar calls federalism's processes. Federation theory, as applied to civics curriculum, has a set of aims. They are:
*Teach a view of government as a supra federated institution of society in which collective interests of the commonwealth are protected and advanced.
*Teach the philosophical basis of government's role as guardian of the grand partnership of citizens at both levels of individuals and associations of political and social intercourse.
*Convey the need of government to engender levels of support promoting a general sense of obligation and duty toward agreed upon goals and processes aimed at advancing the common betterment.
*Establish and justify a political morality which includes a process to assess whether that morality meets the needs of changing times while holding true to federalist values.
*Emphasize the integrity of the individual both in terms of liberty and equity in which each citizen is a member of a compacted arrangement and whose role is legally, politically, and socially congruent with the spirit of the Bill of Rights.
*Find a balance between a respect for national expertise and an encouragement of local, unsophisticated participation in policy decision-making and implementation.
Your input, as to the content of this Blog, is encouraged through this Blog directly or the Blog's email address: gravitascivics@gmail.com .
NOTE: This blog has led to the publication of a book. The title of that book is TOWARD A FEDERATED NATION: IMPLEMENTING NATIONAL CIVICS STANDARDS and it is available through Amazon in both ebook and paperback versions.

Friday, July 14, 2017

BASELINE EQUALITY

The context of this posting was adequately given in the first few paragraphs of the last posting.  To repeat that description, here is how that posting began:
The last series of postings presented, described, and explained the components of a liberated federalism model.  The components are the community, the entities, and the association.  This is an idealistic model – how governance and politics should take place – and its normative quality is defined by federalist values.  Those values revolve around the concern for societal welfare.  Its function is to help guide civics educators in their choice of instructional content.
What remains in this presentation of the model is to comment on how it is “activated.”  The model focuses on an event, when a polity is confronted with a political challenge.  What this and the following postings will address is the substantive issues that usually pose the political challenges an association is likely to encounter, especially when the association is a government.
After that introduction, the posting went on to describe how federation theory views equality.  It offered the following definition for equality:  a belief that despite inequality in personal attributes, such as talent and other resources, each person is entitled to equal consideration of his/her well-being, that all have an equal right to maintain their dignity and integrity as individual persons.  As such, equality has a normative quality since it reflects a respect for being human beyond the biological aspects.[1]
The posting goes on to state that equality, as an element of federation theory, has two forms:  baseline equality and equality of treatment.  The purpose of this posting is to provide a definition for the first of these forms, to make a statement as to its importance, and to indicate the social implications baseline equality form has.
Definition – Baseline equality relates to liberty.  Oftentimes, equality and liberty are presented as opposing ideals, but as federation theory defines them, equality is related and gives context to liberty.  In terms of baseline equality, this aspect refers to the minimal level of equality to which each person is entitled.  This aspect is constitutionally defined.  In relation to this is the jurisprudential development of the Fourteenth Amendment regarding its provision of equal protection[2] and to some degree, due process provisions is relevant.
Importance – This notion of equality adds to the value of liberty.  Its addition is limited to the notion that liberty need not be fixated on the concept of the individual sovereignty.  As noted earlier in this blog, individual sovereignty is the way the natural rights construct defines liberty.  Federation theory instead links liberty to a certain reality, one that is based on the observation that we are all mutually dependent on a communal existence. 
Natural rights’ definition of liberty invites individuals to adopt any value orientation, be it based on religious beliefs, communal concerns, or self-interest; individuals are free in law and expectations to choose whatever basis to determine how they will define their lives, especially in terms of moral commitments.  Hence, that construct sees the individual as sovereign.
Many, if not most, people use a basis of short term self-interest to make these life-defining decisions.  This leaves the interests of the community wanting, which hurts the health of the commonwealth and in the long run the interests of the individual.  This is not a logical result of individual sovereignty, but it is the actual result one can readily see in societies that adopt the natural rights perspective as the dominant view of governance and politics.
Social Implication – Under natural rights’ view of liberty, such a result is determined to be just the way things happen to be.  Perhaps there is a degree of regret, but it is believed among its adherents to just be the price one pays for liberty.  And that view leads to policy biases that shy away from communal based policies; these more socially oriented policy choices are judged as intrusive to individual prerogatives.
Federation theory uses another basis, a more communal perspective.  One might ask:  is it a collectivist perspective or a socialistic view?  Selznick writes concerning the effects of historical actions in relation to the rights of the individual and the interests of the commonwealth:
The constitutional doctrine of equal protection does not ignore or erase differences of talent, achievement, contribution, or good fortune.  It is not a device for leveling gradations or for making society more homogeneous.  It is, however, a path to community.  Equal protection speaks above all to membership, and membership presumes that all who belong share a core identity.  This identity is wholly compatible with rich diversity so long as that diversity does not undermine equality of membership.  The most serious threat to such equality is division based on moral stigma.  Whatever its source, whether it be a certain racial or ethnic origin or level of native intelligence, the effect of moral stigma is to rank some people as intrinsically less worthy than others.  Vindication of moral equality, in the face of strong impulses toward moral hierarchy, is the primary mission of equal protection of the law.[3] (Emphasis in the original)
With such a view of equality, the individual is free – he or she has liberty – to do what he or she should do.
And when one considers what one should do, one introduces a moral approach at least in terms of civic affairs.  Within a community, the expectation is created that all members can fully participate or else there can be no meaningful commonwealth.  Self-interest is not forgotten, but it is tempered with a realization of a communal reality of mutual interests that does make itself felt if only eventually.
This view is counter to the individual sovereignty view espoused by the natural rights construct.  A distinction should be made between those self-interests based behaviors that offends contractual arrangements (an agreed exchange of something for something else) and those that offend understandings within a compact arrangement (an agreement based on a solemn pledge to create and/or advance a collective, an association). 
Many see the former view leading to the behaviors causing the 2008 financial crisis.  Those actions were moral and legal under a natural rights view, they did not offend contractual obligations; but they did offend the federalist provisions of mutual interests and acted against the common good for short-term profit.
Selznick continues that there is not just an expectation of being protected against abuses of power, but equality includes a whole range of duties and rights attached to membership.  While these rights and duties might be bound by limited resources and options – an individual might not possess those levels of assets that others have – they are what make membership meaningful.[4] 
That is, the level of duties and rights are affected by the amount of assets and resources a person has at his/her disposal.  Generally, the more someone benefits, the more his/her duty is.  Rights for the advantaged citizen might be further restrained by being subject to certain policies such as a progressive tax rate.[5]
In terms of federation theory, this notion of liberty needs to be fleshed out.  For one thing, in everyday life, one would not be able to distinguish it from the natural rights view of liberty.  In most cases, one is not talking about a sort of liberty that deprives a person from making life-defining decisions or from enjoying the added entitlements a higher income or wealth level can afford. 
What is being promoted is a public expectation that first takes seriously what can reasonably be demanded from citizens.  This public sphere also provides a language that can be utilized to legitimately evaluate how effectively citizens meet the obligations and duties of being citizens.  And this evaluation considers the various benefits citizens can secure.
A rule of thumb that apply to this sense of liberty is to simply state that everyone can pursue his/her self-interest if a person does not define those interests in such a way as to counter the common good.  Admittedly, at times that might call for significant reflection.  Why? Because often such judgements are difficult and complex.
They are often not even a function of law, but of social norms and other expectations.  For example, many of the super-rich today have chosen to bequeath their fortunes to charitable efforts after their deaths.  Should this be a federated expectation?  It is a legitimate question to ask under the tenets of federation theory.
The next posting will address the second form of a federated equality, equality of treatment or what this account prefers to call regulated condition.



[1] The reader is invited to check out the previous posting (July 11, 2017 entry).

[2] Mark V. Tushnet, “Equal Protection,” in The Oxford Companion to the Supreme Court, ed. Kermit L. Hall (New York NY:  Oxford University Press, 1992), 257-259.

[3] Philip Selznick, The Moral Commonwealth:  Social Theory and the Promise of Community, 489.

[4] Ibid.

[5] As the nation has become more ensconced in a natural rights perspective, calls for a flat tax have become more strident.

No comments:

Post a Comment